Direct Realism

Basic definition.

  • Direct realism , also known as naive realism , posits that perceptions provide direct knowledge of the world.
  • Proponents maintain we experience external objects and their qualities precisely as they truly are .
  • Perceptual experiences are not intermediated by sense-data , contrary to indirect realist or representational views.

Principal Features

  • In the direct realist view , what is perceived is not a representation or an image of the external world, but the world itself.
  • Among advocates, there is a general belief in the existence of a world independent of the human mind.
  • It supports the notion of unmediated contact with the world, suggesting our experiences aren’t manipulated by any internal processes .

Arguments in Favour

  • The argument from perceptual relativity proposes that the variation in perceptual experiences doesn’t necessitate acceptance of sense-data .
  • Hallucinations and illusions , critics argue, can be contextualised as misinterpretations of sensory input rather than as proof of indirect realism.
  • The theory of direct realism dismiss the need for an internal representation to explain perception, aiding Occam’s razor .

Criticisms and Counter-arguments

  • Critics question the direct realist’s ability to account for hallucinations and illusions , where perceptions appear detached from any external object.
  • Critics mention the phenomenon of perceptual variation ; the same object can appear differently to two observers, or to the same observer at different times.
  • Critics further argue that if direct realism were true, we would be able to rely on our senses for accurate information about the world. However, various fields from psychology to physics show that our senses can be misleading .
  • Counter-arguments often focus on theories of perceptual adaptation and advancements in neuroscience to help explain how our perception can be both direct and fallible.

Key Philosophers

  • Significant proponents of direct realism include G.E. Moore and J.L. Austin , who presented detailed arguments against the idea of sense-data and the indirect realism associated with it.
  • Both philosophers argue that our direct experiences are not complex interpretations or representations, but an immediate engagement with the world.
  • While not without critics, direct realism forms a substantial part of epistemological theories, and it is important to understand both the arguments for and against this perspective.

A Level Philosophy & Religious Studies

Perception as a source of knowledge

AQA Philosophy Epistemology

Direct realism

Direct realism is the common sense intuitive view that the objects of perception are physical objects which exist independently of our minds. We think of Physical objects as existing objectively in space and time. If I am in a room and perceive some physical objects in it, then when I leave the room they remain as they are unless they are undergoing some sort of physical process like burning which would cause them to change when I wasn’t there to perceive them.

Direct realism claims that our senses perceive those physical objects and their properties. For example, when perceiving the physical object of table, I perceive it’s properties such as color, shape, size, smell and texture.

The perceptual variation issue for direct realism

Bertrand Russell argued that what we perceive is not the same as what is in reality and so direct realism is false. Russell points to the example of a shiny, brown table. He argues that the color of the table actually depends on where you stand in relation to it. There is light falling on the table making a part of it shiny and therefore white in color in a certain spot, but if another person were to stand at a different place to you, that white spot would appear to them to be on a different part of the table than where it appears to you. Therefore, where one person sees the table to be white, another might see it to be brown. A particular spot on an object cannot be two colours at once, therefore colour cannot be a property of the table.

Russell argues this can apply to texture too. While the table feels smooth, on a macroscopic level it has indentations and grooves. Shape is also perceptually variable since it depends on the angle at which you view the table as to whether it looks square or rectangular.

Integration: direct realism is false in its claim that the properties we perceive are properties of a mind-independent object. Our perceptions must be mind-dependent sense data instead of direct perception of mind-independent objects.

P1. Our perception of an object can vary without any corresponding change in the object. C1. Therefore, there is a difference between the properties that physical objects appear to have and the properties they really have. C2. Therefore, what we perceive and what exists mind-independently are different. C2. Therefore, the immediate objects of perception and their properties are different to what exists mind-independently. C3. Therefore, direct realism is false.

Direct realists can respond by arguing that perceptual variation is the result of perceiving relational properties of mind-independent physical objects.

There are two types of relational properties:

  • Relational properties between objects: properties that objects have in virtue of their relation to other objects. E.g.: being “hotter than” is a relational property the Sun has to the earth.
  • Perceptual perceptual relational properties: properties that objects have due to to being perceived. E.g.: The property of “looking square” or “looking rectangular”

It is the second type of relational property that explains perceptual variation. Since the relation of an object to a perceiver can change, so too can the perceptual relational properties that the object has.

Integration: this response from direct realists denies the inference from P1 to C1. Perceptual relational properties are directly percieved properties of an object, but it only has them through being percieved. So, our perceptions can involve relational properties that can vary without a corresponding change in the physical object (P1 is correct). Yet, this does not show that there is a difference between the properties an object really has verses appears to have (the inference to C1 does not follow). An object could have the relational property of ‘looking rectangular’ while also having the intrinsic property of ‘being square’.

Indirect realists can attempt to respond. These perceptual relational properties are mind-dependent. Without a mind perceiving them, they would not exist. So, relational properties are dependent on minds. So, contra direct realism, when perceiving relational properties we cannot be perceiving properties “ of” mind-independent objects or properties that they “ have ”. Relational properties are properties which an object is only perceived to have, not properties intrinsic to the object.

Integration: such properties must be of sense data; mind-dependent representations, rather than direct perceptions. It follows that in cases of perceptual variation, a direct realist cannot claim that they are perceiving mind-independent objects and “their” properties. So, direct realism is false.

However, direct realists can respond that there are two ways a perceptual relational property can be mind-dependent:

  • Mind dependent due to being a property of sense data.
  • Mind dependent due to requiring a mind to exist.

Indirect realists are trying to argue that relational properties are mind-dependent in the first way. Yet, direct realists can respond that they are only mind-dependent in the second way and that this second way does not conflict with direct realism.

The direct realist claims that the objects of perception are mind-independent objects and their properties. We perceive properties of mind-independent objects.  Perceptual relational properties may depend on minds, but nonetheless they are still properties that objects have due to their relation to a perceiver. They cannot only be properties of sense-data, since they do require an objective relation to an object. It is only from a particular angle that a square object could have the relational property of ‘looking rectangular’. So, indirect realists cannot say that the relational properties are mind-dependent in the way of being a property of sense data, i.e., exist only in the mind. It seems they actually belong to the objective relation between a subjective mind and an objective object.

Although perceptual relational properties are not intrinsic to an object, they are intrinsic to the relation between the object and a perceiver. They are mind-dependent, since the perceiver is essential to the existence of the property, but equally, so is the object. It isn’t correct to suggest that such properties only belong to the perceiver, i.e., only in the mind. They involve something objective about the relation between an object and a perceiver. Ultimately, it seems that perceptual relational properties belong both to an object and its perceiver. They involve an objective relation between a subjective mind and an objective object.

Integration: so, direct realism can be defended in its claim that perceptual variation can be explained through perceptual relational properties that are properties of mind-dependent objects. A mind-independent object can have relational properties that depend on a mind to exist.

The illusion issue for direct realism

If you look at a straight stick submerged in a glass of water, the light-refracting properties of water make it look bent. An illusion occurs when an object (the stick) appears to have a property (of bentness) yet in reality it does not have that property (It isn’t bent). Therefore, the perceived illusory property is sense data which exists in the mind, not reality. Illusions appear just as real as normal veridical perceptions – they are subjectively indistinguishable. Therefore, normal perceptions must also be of sense data in the mind, not of physical objects. So direct realism is false.

P1. During an illusion, I observe an object p with property y . P2. According to direct realism, if I perceive property y , then property y exists mind-independently. P3. During an illusion, there is no property y . C1. Therefore, our perception of the property y of object p must be mind-dependent sense data. P4. Illusions can be subjectively indistinguishable from veridical perceptions. C2. Therefore, in all cases, the objects of perception and their properties are mind-dependent sense data. C3. Therefore, direct realism is false.

The direct realist could respond by appealing to relational properties. A relational property is one that a thing has by virtue of its relation to something else. The stick could have the relational property of looking bent to a certain observer under certain conditions (such as being observed through water). This is a (relational) property that the stick has. So, observing a stick bent in water does involve observing a mind-independent object and its properties and therefore direct realism is not shown to be false by illusions.

The hallucination issue for direct realism

Hallucination occurs when perceiving an object that doesn’t exist. Therefore, what we perceived must be mind-dependent sense data. Hallucinations are subjectively indistinguishable from normal veridical perceptions, therefore normal perceptions must also be of sense data, not mind-independent physical objects. So direct realism is false.

P1. During a hallucination I observe an object p . P2. According to direct realism, if I perceive object p , then object p exists mind-independently. P3. During a hallucination there is no physical object p . C1. Therefore, the object of perception p must be mind-dependent sense data. P4. Hallucinations can be subjectively indistinguishable from veridical perception. C2. Therefore, in all cases, the objects of perception are mind-dependent sense data. C3. Therefore, direct realism is false.

Direct realists can respond with the disjunctive theory of perception. A disjunction is when there are two possible ways something can be. It is either one or the other. Hallucination is very different from normal veridical perception as it involves a mind separated from reality. Therefore this case is disjunctive as it must be either/or – it cannot be both – the mind is either connected to reality or separated. So, what we perceive is either a hallucination from our imagination or a veridical perception of reality. Just because those two possibilities appear the same, it doesn’t mean they are the same. In fact, since they are disjunctive, they cannot be the same. Therefore, just because hallucinatory cases are of mind-dependent sense data, it doesn’t follow that all perceptions are mind-dependent sense data too.

Integration: The disjunctive theory of perception shows the possibility that that when hallucinating we are experiencing the product of our imagination. We experience object p but there is no object p. Direct realists can thereby deny P1 and P2, that when we perceive an object p that there is something that is p.

The time-lag argument against direct realism

It takes time for light to reach us from an object we perceive. The light from the stars we see in the sky may have taken billions of years to reach earth. So we see those stars as they were billions of years ago, not as they are now. Although the objects of perception we more regularly see are much closer, like a table or chair, the light still takes some time to reach us. Therefore, we are not seeing the objects of perception directly, we are seeing them as they were in the past. Therefore, direct realism is false.

Indirect Realism

Indirect realism is the view that the objects of perception are a mind-dependent representation which is caused by external mind-independent physical objects. Sense-data is perceived immediately (directly) whereas physical objects are perceived indirectly. The representation can be different from the object it represents. The argument from perceptual variation, illusion and hallucination, which try to show that what we see isn’t necessarily the reality, argue for indirect realism

Russell defines sense-data as the ‘content’ of our immediate sensory perception.

John Locke’s primary/secondary quality distinction

Locke claims that the objects of perception have primary qualities which are ‘intrinsic’ to the object and secondary qualities which are just in our mind. Primary qualities are shape, extension, number, movement. Secondary qualities are colour, taste, smell, touch.

Locke argues for this distinction by pointing to the case of a grain of wheat. If you continually divide a grain of wheat, eventually it will become insensible, having no colour, taste, smell or touch. However, it will still have a shape, extension, number or movement. This shows that secondary qualities are separable from an object, whereas primary qualities are not.

Indirect Realism issue: Scepticism about the existence of mind-independent objects

Indirect realism claims that the objects of perception are mind-dependent sense data that represents and is caused by mind-independent objects.

However, if all we perceive directly are sense-data, then we never perceive the mind-independent objects which Indirect realists claim are giving rise to and being represented by that sense-data.

There is a ‘veil of perception’ between our sense data and the external world through which we cannot perceive. In that case, it seems we can’t actually know that mind-independent objects exist at all, let alone whether sense data represents them.

For example, solipsism could be true; that only my mind exists and my perceptual experience is caused by my imagination.

Integration: The first claim of indirect realism, that the objects of perception are mind-dependent sense data, undermines our ability to justifiably know the second claim, that sense data is caused by and represents mind-independent objects. So, direct realism is epistemologically self-defeating and we can never be justified in believing it.

Russell’s best hypothesis response to the issue of scepticism

Russell argued we can neither prove nor disprove either the claim that the external world exists and causes my sense data, or the claim that the external world does not exist and so does not cause my sense data. Since we cannot prove for certain either claim, we are left with making a hypothesis (a theory which is confirmed or disconfirmed by experience or reason). Russell argues the question then becomes which possibility – that the external world exists or does not – is the best hypothesis.

Russell points to the example of a cat. When first you glance, it is in a corner of the room. The next time you look, it is on a sofa. If there is no external world, then the cat just disappeared from one place in perceptual experience and then appeared in another. However that does not provide an explanation of the experience as there is no reason why that should happen. If we take the other hypothesis, that there is an external world so the cat is a mind-independent object which continues existing when unperceived, then we have an explanation of our sense data of the cat having moved to the sofa – it walked there when you weren’t looking! Since this hypothesis actually explains our experience, it is the better explanation and so, Russell concludes it is the best hypothesis.

However, Russell’s argument can be responded to. Why is the cat having its own mind-independent existence really a ‘better’ explanation of our experience? What criteria is Russell using to judge that? It makes more sense ‘to us’, but that could just be because of our habit of thinking that there is an external world. If we discount that, it’s hard to see what possible reason we could have to prefer Russell’s explanation to the explanation of solipsism – the view that only our mind exists and the physical world does not. Both explanations are equally consistent with any and all experience, therefore there is no justification to prefer either and thus no way to say which explanation is better, so Russell’s ‘best hypothesis’ argument fails.

John Locke’s argument from the involuntary nature of our experience

Locke argues that perceptions from sense experience have a key difference to perceptions from memory or imagination in that we have no choice over what we perceive in sense-data. However, we can choose what to remember or imagine. If there really were no external world causing our sense-data, then everything must be in our mind. In that case, we should expect to have choice over perceptions from sense experience. However we do not – if we look at a bottle of water we have no choice but to see one. Yet if we want to imagine a bottle of water filled with gold or remember the last time we drank from one, we can. Since we have choice over perceptions which originate from our mind yet we have no choice from those from sense experience, it follows that perceptions from sense experience do not originate from our mind but from an external world.

The argument from the coherence of various kinds of experience (Locke & Cockburne)

Locke also argues that sense-data from different senses back each other up. E.g if I see an apple, I can touch it to see if it also feels like one, and taste it to see if it also tastes like one.

Locke combines these two arguments in the example of changing how paper looks by writing on it – so sight and the sense of your hand moving cohere. You cannot cause the words to appear on the paper by mere imagination, you have to actually write. Once it is written, it cannot be changed except by further writing. If someone else read out what you had written, there would be coherence between your auditory (hearing) sense-data and what you thought to write. Lock argues this ‘leaves little reason for doubt’ that there is an external world.

Catherine Cockburn also responds to scepticism about the existence of mind-independent objects with an argument from experiential coherence. She first points to the radical difference between experiences gained from different senses. E.g. The sound a waterfall makes is not just different to but of a very different sort than the visual experience of it. Cockburn then points out we learn to pair visual and auditory experiences together such that we are able to make an inference from one to the other. If we are walking on a mountain and hear a waterfall, we can infer and accurately predict what it looks like; and vice versa, if we see a waterfall from far away, we can infer and accurately predict what it will sound like when we have moved closer. The fact that we can accurately infer and predict our experiences suggests that there is some mind-independent object which both senses perceive yet is independent of any particular sense. If it could be heard without being seen and seen without being heard, then it seems to follow it exists without being seen or heard, i.e. mind-independently.

Arguably however Locke hasn’t proven that there is an external world of physical objects, he has merely given some reasons as to how it makes sense of our sense-data for there to be one. Locke claims the fact that we have no choice over our sense-data perceptions shows they are not a part of our mind. However, this is to assume all parts of our mind are under our control. There might be some reason unknown to us why sense-data originating from our mind isn’t under our control. There might also be some reason why we get the same information from different senses, despite them also potentially originating from our mind.

Nonetheless, indirect realism can still be justified by Locke’s arguments if we use Russell’s notion that it is the best hypothesis. The existence of the external world is the best explanation of lack of choice over perceptions and the coherence of various senses.

The argument from Berkeley that we cannot know the nature of mind-independent objects because mind-dependent objects cannot be like mind-independent objects

Indirect realism relies on the claim that our perceptions are mind-dependent sense data which represents mind-independent objects. Berkeley attacks this claim with the likeness principle, which states that to justifiably say that two things to be alike, they must be comparable. But, ideas (mind-dependent) can only be compared to other ideas. There is no way to compare ideas to mind-independent objects and so resemblance between them cannot be justifiably claimed.

Integration: this issue attacks the claim of indirect realism that the objects of perception represent mind-independent objects.

An indirect realist can respond that Berkeley assumes that representation requires resemblance. Arguably there are other methods of representation. For example, the symbols we use in language are completely arbitrary, meaning they have no resemblance to the objects they refer to. The word ‘chair’ does not resemble a chair but nonetheless can represent it. So, mind-dependent objects can be ‘like’ mind-independent objects if we take ‘like’ to involve representation without resemblance.

However, we could defend Berkeley by taking   his argument to not be attacking whether an idea could be like a mind-independent object, but whether we could ever be in a position to know that it does. Berkeley seems to be saying that in order for a person to know that an idea is like a mind-independent object, they would have to compare them, yet that cannot be done since we have no direct perception of mind-independent objects. So, no one can justifiably claim that ideas represent mind-independent objects and therefore indirect realism cannot be justified.

Even if we restrict ‘likeness’ to representation, nonetheless our perceptions might not even represent the mind-independent world. It could be totally unlike our perceptions in any respect.

So, we just cannot know whether our perceptions represent mind-independent objects. Indirect realism leads to this sceptical issue, therefore.

Berkeley’s idealism

Berkeley’s attack on the primary/secondary quality distinction, berkeley’s master argument, idealism and the issue of illusions.

Idealism claims we perceive ideas directly as they are because to be is to be perceived. The result seems to be that, for example, when we perceive an object like a stick in water appearing bent that it really is bent. Yet, If we reach into the glass to feel that the stick is straight, while also looking at the stick appearing bent, then we perceive two inconstant properties at the same time. It cannot be the case that the stick is both bent and straight. At most one of those properties can be the reality and the other must therefore be an appearance, i.e., sense data. It follows that there is a distinction between appearance and reality. So, it is not the case that to be is to be perceived and therefore Berkeley’s Idealism is false.

Integration: Idealism fails in its claim that to be is to be perceived, which means it is not the case that the objects of perception are mind-dependent ideas.

Berkeley responds that this is a mistake in the language we use to talk about the situation. When we say ‘the stick is bent’ what Berkeley argues we really mean is that it would look bent under normal conditions, which is clearly false. Berkeley suggests instead saying “the stick looks bent”, which is clearly true. An indirect realist would want to insist that although the stick ‘looks’ bent, it isn’t ‘really’ bent – but that is to presuppose that there is a distinction between appearance and reality, which Berkeley has already denied in his attack on the primary/secondary quality distinction. Illusion is only a problem for a theory if it claims that the stick looks bent but is really straight. For Berkeley, there is no way a thing “really is” aside from how it is perceived. It’s not that he denies that it is “really” straight, it’s that he denies there is any way the stick “really is” aside from how it “looks”; how it is perceived.

Integration: Berkeley denies the inference from the stick looking bent to the claim that the stick really is straight. This is a confusion over what Berkeley meant by ‘to be is to be perceived’. To be bent is merely to look bent, not to possess a quality of bentness.

The argument from illusion against idealism begs the question by assuming that there is a distinction between appearance and reality, i.e., a way the stick really is aside from how it appears. The conclusion that idealism leads to an inconsistency between appearance and reality is based on that assumption, which Berkeley does not have to accept. Indeed, in his master argument and attack on the primary/secondary quality distinction he thinks he has given us reason to disregard that assumption.

Idealism and the issue of hallucinations

A hallucination is the perception of an object which doesn’t exist. The possibility of hallucinations pose a problem for idealism because they are subjectively indistinguishable from veridical perceptions. For Berkeley, a veridical perception is when we perceive an idea that is in the mind of God. Yet, hallucinations according to Berkeley come from our imagination, not from God’s mind. While the imagination normally produces voluntary and relatively dim perceptions which are not vivid, Berkeley argues that at times it can produce involuntary and vivid perceptions.

The problem is, if some perceptions are hallucinations from our imagination and they are subjectively indistinguishable from other perceptions, then we can’t tell the difference between hallucination and reality (reality being an idea in the mind of God).

Integration: Berkeley has an epistemological issue, an issue with scepticism, which is a problem for Berkeley as he claimed that defeating scepticism was a reason to accept his theory over indirect realism.

Berkeley responds that hallucinations lack logical connection to the rest of our experience.

However, this response is unsuccessful because some hallucinations might be logically connected to the rest of our experience however. Someone with a fever might look out a window and hallucinate a person walking down the street. There is nothing illogical about that and so no way to tell.

Idealism and the issue of solipsism

Berkeley’s arguments for Idealism conclude that the the objects of perception are mind dependent ideas. When we perceive a mountain or a tree, they have no mind-independent existence as they are just ideas in my mind. The problem is that it’s difficult to see how this would not apply to other people too. It follows that other people are therefore just ideas in my mind. This is called solipsism, the sceptical view that I can only know that my mind exists.

Integration: this issue does not suggest that Idealism is false. It only shows that Idealism leads to this sceptical issue. It somewhat undermines Berkeley’s claim that his theory is superior to the realist theories because it solves issues of epistemological scepticism.

However, Berkeley thinks that Idealism provides an argument for God’s existence which would show that solipsism is false since God also exists, not just my mind.

In the Dialogues, Berkeley argues that God must exist because our ideas must exist in God when not perceived by us. The complexity and regularity of the ideas we perceive shows that they come from God’s mind.

Idealism faces the issue of explaining the regularity of our perceptions, including their apparent continued existence when unperceived.

If I throw a lit match into an empty room, leave it and come back later, the room will have changed.

According to Berkeley however, ‘to be is to be perceived’. Since the room is unperceived it does not exist, yet Idealism is then left with the problem of explaining how it could have undergone change.

Berkeley solves this problem by claiming that God perceives the room and indeed everything other idea, thereby keeping them in existence regardless of whether any human is observing them.

In the Principles, Berkeley argues that once Idealism is established to be true, an argument for God follows as the required causal explanation of our ideas.

If Idealism is true, our ideas cannot be caused by mind-independent objects. The only other options are that they are caused by other ideas, our own minds or another mind.

Ideas are perceived to be passive, to have no causal power, and since to be is to be perceived, ideas have no causal power.

I can cause some ideas through imagination, but others are involuntary and therefore cannot come from my mind.

So by process of elimination, the third option must be true. The involuntary ideas we experience must come from another mind. Berkeley argues that the immeasurable complexity and regularity of the ideas we experience shows that this other mind must be far greater than our own, i.e., God.

This alone counters Solipsism since if God’s mind exists then my mind is not the only mind. However, Berkeley also argues we at least have some evidence to justify thinking other people have minds too. We can infer that on the basis of our own experience of them.

However, If Berkeley’s attack on the primary/secondary quality distinction and master argument fail to establish idealism, or if some other argument proves idealism false, however, then his inference of God would likewise fail. Berkeley’s defence against solipsism relies on his proof of God, which relies on his arguments for idealism. It’s only if Idealism is true that God’s existence is required to explain the regularity of our perceptions and that therefore my mind is not the only one which exists.

Whether God can be used to play the role that he does in Berkeley’s idealism

In Berkeley’s Idealism, God plays the role of perceiving all ideas and causing our ideas. However, since this involves those ideas being in God’s mind, this leads to an issue.

The idea that God could have the same ideas as us is problematic for the traditional view of God. It would mean that God could experience pain, for example. God cannot suffer. Furthermore, God’s ideas are eternal yet ours are transient. God also has ideas of all possible objects, not just the ones that we experience.

Integration: so, it cannot be the case that our ideas originate from God’s mind. Berkeley is therefore left with the sceptical issues of solipsism and accounting for the origin and regularity of our ideas, including their changing when unperceived.

  • International
  • Schools directory
  • Resources Jobs Schools directory News Search

AQA A-Level Philosophy Direct Realism

AQA A-Level Philosophy Direct Realism

Subject: Philosophy and ethics

Age range: 16+

Resource type: Assessment and revision

jadeeveberry

Last updated

8 June 2020

  • Share through email
  • Share through twitter
  • Share through linkedin
  • Share through facebook
  • Share through pinterest

docx, 17.1 KB

AQA A-Level Philosphy 25 mark essay, plan, mark scheme and 5-mark questions Essay titled ‘Can direct realism survive its criticisms’ and is marked as a band 5 essay (21-25 marks) This resource also includes a complete set of 5 mark questions and answers for Direct Realism

Tes paid licence How can I reuse this?

Your rating is required to reflect your happiness.

It's good to leave some feedback.

Something went wrong, please try again later.

This resource hasn't been reviewed yet

To ensure quality for our reviews, only customers who have purchased this resource can review it

Report this resource to let us know if it violates our terms and conditions. Our customer service team will review your report and will be in touch.

Not quite what you were looking for? Search by keyword to find the right resource:

  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Knowing by Perceiving

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

3 Perception, Experience, and Direct Realism

  • Published: January 2019
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Direct Realism is the thesis that our perception of mind-independent things is routinely direct. It is true if and only if, routinely, our perception of mind-independent things is not by means of perceiving something that is distinct and separate from those things. This chapter defends Direct Realism. It begins with an examination of reasons that have been given in the past for rejecting it, focusing on Hume and G. E. Moore. There follows a discussion of relationalist versus non-relationalist conceptions of perceptual experience. Particular attention is given to reconciling a non-relationalist conception with Direct Realism. To this end discussion is focused on how perception facilitates perceptual–demonstrative thought. An important role is played by a view of how to understand non-committal descriptions of experiences. This view figures in a response to problems raised by Michael Martin for non-relationist conceptions of experience.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]
  • Google Scholar Indexing

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code

Institutional access

  • Sign in with a library card Sign in with username/password Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Sign in through your institution

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Sign in with a library card

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

This website works best with JavaScript switched on. Please enable JavaScript

  • Centre Services
  • Associate Extranet
  • All About Maths

A-level Philosophy

  • Specification
  • Teaching resources
  • Assessment resources
  • Introduction
  • Specification at a glance

3.1 Epistemology

  • 3.2 Moral philosophy
  • 3.3 Metaphysics of God
  • 3.4 Metaphysics of mind
  • Scheme of assessment
  • General administration

 Epistemology

What is knowledge?

  • The distinction between acquaintance knowledge, ability knowledge and propositional knowledge.
  • The nature of definition (including Linda Zagzebski) and how propositional knowledge may be analysed/defined.

The tripartite view 

Propositional knowledge is defined as justified true belief: S knows that p if and only if:

  • S is justified in believing that p,
  • p is true and
  • S believes that p (individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions)

Issues with the tripartite view including:

  • the conditions are not individually necessary
  • responses: alternative post-Gettier analyses/definitions of knowledge including:
  • strengthen the justification condition (ie infallibilism)
  • add a 'no false lemmas' condition (J+T+B+N)
  • replace 'justified' with 'reliably formed' (R+T+B) (ie reliabilism)
  • replace 'justified' with an account of epistemic virtue (V+T+B).

Perception as a source of knowledge

Direct realism.

The immediate objects of perception are mind-independent objects and their properties

Issues including:

  • the argument from illusion
  • the argument from perceptual variation
  • the argument from hallucination
  • the time-lag argument

and responses to these issues.

Indirect realism

The immediate objects of perception are mind-dependent objects (sense-data) that are caused by and represent mind-independent objects.

  • John Locke's primary/secondary quality distinction.
  • Locke's argument from the involuntary nature of our experience
  • the argument from the coherence of various kinds of experience, as developed by Locke and Catharine Trotter Cockburn (attrib)
  • Bertrand Russell's response that the external world is the 'best hypothesis'
  • the argument from George Berkeley that we cannot know the nature of mind-independent objects because mind-dependent ideas cannot be like mind-independent objects.

Berkeley's Idealism

The immediate objects of perception (ie ordinary objects such as tables, chairs, etc) are mind-dependent objects.

  • Arguments for idealism including Berkeley's attack on the primary/secondary quality distinction and his 'Master' argument.
  • arguments from illusion and hallucination
  • idealism leads to solipsism
  • problems with the role played by God in Berkeley's Idealism (including how can Berkeley claim that our ideas exist within God's mind given that he believes that God cannot feel pain or have sensations?)

Reason as a source of knowledge

Arguments from Plato (ie the 'slave boy' argument) and Gottfried Leibniz (ie his argument based on necessary truths).

Empiricist responses including:

  • Locke's arguments against innatism
  • the mind as a 'tabula rasa' (the nature of impressions and ideas, simple and complex concepts)

and issues with these responses.

The intuition and deduction thesis

  • The meaning of ‘intuition’ and ‘deduction’ and the distinction between them.
  • René Descartes’ notion of ‘clear and distinct ideas’.
  • His cogito as an example of an a priori intuition.
  • His arguments for the existence of God and his proof of the external world as examples of a priori deductions.
  • responses to Descartes' cogito
  • responses to Descartes' arguments for the existence of God and his proof of the external world (including how Hume's Fork might be applied to these arguments)

The limits of knowledge

  • Particular nature of philosophical scepticism and the distinction between philosophical scepticism and normal incredulity.
  • The role/function of philosophical scepticism within epistemology
  • The distinction between local and global scepticism and the (possible) global application of philosophical scepticism
  • Descartes’ sceptical arguments (the three ‘waves of doubt’)
  • Descartes' own response
  • empiricist responses (Locke, Berkeley and Russell)
  • reliabilism.

Berkeley, George (1713), Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous

Descartes, René (1641), Meditations on First Philosophy, 1, 2, 3, 5, 6

Gettier, Edmund (1963), ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’ Analysis, 23(6): 121–123

Hume, David (1748), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Section 2 and Section 4 (part 1)

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1705), New Essays on Human Understanding, Preface and Book 1

Locke, John (1690), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Book 1 (esp. Chapter 2), Book 2 (esp. Chapters 1, 2, 8 and 14), Book 4 (esp. Chapter 11)

Plato, Meno, from 81e

Russell, Bertrand (1912), The Problems of Philosophy, Chapters 1, 2

Trotter Cockburn, Catharine (1732), (attrib) ‘A Letter from an anonymous writer to the author of the Minute Philosopher’ Appendix to G Berkeley Theory of Vision Vindicated and Explained

Zagzebski, Linda (1999), ‘What is Knowledge?’ in John Greco & Ernest Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology 92 –116

Outline the argument from illusion against direct realism

According to direct realism, we perceive objects in the external world directly. This is contrasted with indirect realism, which holds that the immediate objects of perception are mental representations or sense data that represent objects in the external world. Direct realism does not deny that perception involves perhaps quite complex causal chains, where e.g. photons must travel from the object to my retina; but it holds that the photons, the pattern of stimulation on the retina, etc, are not themselves perceived but are part of the mechanism of perception. ¶ The argument from illusion rests on the phenomenal principle, which states that if an object appears to you to have some property F, then what you are directly perceiving does in fact have property F. Consider looking at a stick half-submerged in water. By the phenomenal principle, it follows that you are directly perceiving something that is bent. But the stick itself is not bent, nor is any other mind-independent object in the vicinity bent. Therefore, you are not directly perceiving any mind-independent object when you look at the stick. The next step of the argument claims that illusory experiences and veridical perception should be explained in terms of the same theory of perception. So, since we do not directly perceive mind-independent objects during illusions, we also do not directly perceive mind-independent objects in veridical perception.

14708 Views

Related Philosophy A Level answers

What does it mean for an argument to be valid, what is a deontological ethical theory, why did descartes employ skepticism in his search for knowledge, 'what is the difference between ethical naturalism and non-naturalism's account of moral language', we're here to help, company information, popular requests, © mytutorweb ltd 2013– 2024.

CEOP logo

Internet Safety

Payment Security

Cyber Essentials logo

logo-home

Written for

Document information, connected book.

  • Related courses
  • Epistemology (7172)

Summary AQA A Level Philosophy - Direct Realism A* Notes

  • Institution
  • Philosophy for AS and A Level

Topic summary / notes on direct realism for AQA A Level Philosophy paper 1 epistemology section. These notes were made according to the layout of the specification and were largely helpful as part of my studies for which I received an A* in 2021.

Preview 1 out of 4  pages

mobile-preview

  •   Report Copyright Violation

Preview 1 out of 4 pages

  • Summarized whole book? No
  • Which chapters are summarized? Unknown
  • Uploaded on June 3, 2022
  • Number of pages 4
  • Written in 2020/2021
  • Type Summary
  • epistemology
  • direct realism

direct realism essay a level

Book Title: Philosophy for AS and A Level

Author(s): Michael Lacewing

  • Edition: 2017-06-13
  • ISBN: 9781138690394

More summaries for

  • Summary Intuition and deduction (AS PHILOSOPHY A* NOTES AQA)
  • Exam (elaborations) Meta ethics (EXAM FULL BUNDLE)
  • Summary Direct realism full notes and exam questions
  • Study Level A/AS Level
  • Examinator AQA
  • Subject Philosophy
  • Unit Epistemology (7172)

avatar-seller

Reviews received

The benefits of buying summaries with stuvia:.

Guaranteed quality through customer reviews

Guaranteed quality through customer reviews

Stuvia customers have reviewed more than 700,000 summaries. This how you know that you are buying the best documents.

Quick and easy check-out

Quick and easy check-out

You can quickly pay through credit card for the summaries. There is no membership needed.

Focus on what matters

Focus on what matters

Your fellow students write the study notes themselves, which is why the documents are always reliable and up-to-date. This ensures you quickly get to the core!

Frequently asked questions

What do i get when i buy this document.

You get a PDF, available immediately after your purchase. The purchased document is accessible anytime, anywhere and indefinitely through your profile.

Satisfaction guarantee: how does it work?

Our satisfaction guarantee ensures that you always find a study document that suits you well. You fill out a form, and our customer service team takes care of the rest.

Who am I buying these notes from?

Stuvia is a marketplace, so you are not buying this document from us, but from seller michael6. Stuvia facilitates payment to the seller.

Will I be stuck with a subscription?

No, you only buy these notes for £5.49. You're not tied to anything after your purchase.

Can Stuvia be trusted?

4.6 stars on Google & Trustpilot (+1000 reviews)

91464 documents were sold in the last 30 days

Founded in 2010, the go-to place to buy revision notes and other study material for 14 years now

direct realism essay a level

Skip to content

Get Revising

Join get revising, already a member, direct realism.

The notes are for the AS Philosophy unit 2 exam for AQA. A summary of the arguments which you can use for and against direct realism. 

  • Created by: Sarah
  • Created on: 20-05-12 18:29

No comments have yet been made

Similar Philosophy resources:

Indirect Realism Overview 4.5 / 5 based on 2 ratings

Knowledge of The External World 4.0 / 5 based on 1 rating

Knowledge of the external world 2.0 / 5 based on 2 ratings

Epistemology 5.0 / 5 based on 2 ratings

Direct/Naive Realism 5.0 / 5 based on 3 ratings

Direct realism 0.0 / 5

Epistemology - Perception 2 Markers 0.0 / 5

Knowledge of the External World 3.0 / 5 based on 1 rating

KNOWLEDGE OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD 0.0 / 5

AS Philosophy 2.0 / 5 based on 2 ratings

Related discussions on The Student Room

  • A Level Philosophy 25 marker - please help! »
  • AQA A Level Philosophy Paper 1 7172/1 - 19 May 2022 [Exam Chat] »
  • A-level Philosophy Study Group 2022-2023 »
  • Realism 30 marker Help - sociology ALEVEL »
  • AQA A Level Philosophy Paper 1 + 2 (7172/1+2) 18th and 26th May 2023 [Exam Chat] »
  • issues and debates »
  • Writing a book »
  • Sociology AQA ALevel »
  • youtube channels for philosophy a level »
  • sociology »

direct realism essay a level

Philosophy A Level

Indirect Realism

£ 2.99

Is indirect realism a convincing theory of perception? (25 marks)

This question is asking you to discuss indirect realism (the theory of perception which says a mind-independent external world exists and that we perceive it indirectly via mind-dependent sense data) and argue either that it is the correct theory of perception or that it is an incorrect theory of perception.

Similar questions:

  • Assess indirect realism. (25 marks)
  • “The immediate objects of perception are mind-dependent sense data that is caused by and represents mind-independent objects.” Discuss. (25 marks)

Description

An A* grade example answer to a 25 mark question on indirect realism. This document also includes a bullet-point essay plan to help students understand how to structure their essays for maximum marks.

After completing your purchase, a download link will be sent to the email address used at checkout. If you cannot see this email, please check your spam folder or refer to our order FAQ .

COMMENTS

  1. Direct Realism

    Basic Definition. Direct realism, also known as naive realism, posits that perceptions provide direct knowledge of the world. Proponents maintain we experience external objects and their qualities precisely as they truly are. Perceptual experiences are not intermediated by sense-data, contrary to indirect realist or representational views.

  2. Knowledge from Perception

    This A level philosophy topic looks at 3 theories of perception that explain how we can acquire knowledge from experience, i.e. a posteriori. They are: The theories disagree over such issues as whether the external world exists (realism vs. anti-realism) and the way we perceive it (direct vs. indirect).

  3. Model essay plans for theories of perception

    Model essay plans for theories of perception. Note that this model essay plan is merely one possible way to write an essay on this topic. Points highlighted in light blue are integration points. Points highlighted in green are weighting points. This page contains essay plans for Direct realism, Indirect realism and Idealism.

  4. Perception as a source of knowledge

    Integration: so, direct realism can be defended in its claim that perceptual variation can be explained through perceptual relational properties that are properties of mind-dependent objects. A mind-independent object can have relational properties that depend on a mind to exist. The illusion issue for direct realism

  5. PDF EPISTEMOLOGY

    A. Direct realism Direct realism is the natural starting point for theories of perception. It is common sense to say that we perceive physical objects, and these exist independently of our minds. 'Physical objects' include tables, books, our own bodies, plants, mountains. Cosmology and

  6. AQA A-Level Philosophy Direct Realism

    docx, 15.79 KB. docx, 16.21 KB. docx, 13.87 KB. AQA A-Level Philosphy. 25 mark essay, plan, mark scheme and 5-mark questions. Essay titled 'Can direct realism survive its criticisms' and is marked as a band 5 essay (21-25 marks) This resource also includes a complete set of 5 mark questions and answers for Direct Realism.

  7. AQA Philosophy A Level Revision Notes

    Below are links to A level philosophy revision notes organised by module and topic. The AQA philosophy syllabus (course code 7172) is divided into four modules: ... Direct realism. Problems for direct realism: The argument from perceptual variation; ... Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Arguments against innate knowledge.

  8. 3 Perception, Experience, and Direct Realism

    Direct Realism is the thesis that our perception of mind-independent things is routinely direct. It is true if and only if, routinely, our perception of mind-independent things is not by means of perceiving something that is distinct and separate from those things. This chapter defends Direct Realism. It begins with an examination of reasons ...

  9. AQA

    A-level Philosophy. 7172. ... Direct realism. The immediate objects of perception are mind-independent objects and their properties . ... Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1705), New Essays on Human Understanding, Preface and Book 1. Locke, John (1690), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Book 1 (esp. Chapter 2), Book 2 (esp. Chapters 1, 2, 8 ...

  10. AS Philosophy- Direct Realism

    Created by: emma. Created on: 16-04-13 18:38. Fullscreen. Direct Realism. 'DR' - Believe that what we see, hear or smell is exactly as the way that we perceive. This means that we perceive objects directly. Because they are exactly what we think they are. They also believe that objects exist independent of our minds, therefore if a tree falls ...

  11. Outline the argument from illusion against direct realism

    Outline the argument from illusion against direct realism. According to direct realism, we perceive objects in the external world directly. This is contrasted with indirect realism, which holds that the immediate objects of perception are mental representations or sense data that represent objects in the external world. Direct realism does not ...

  12. PDF Get help and support A-LEVEL EXAMPLE PHILOSOPHY RESPONSES

    A-level (7172) Marked Papers. 7172 See a range of responses and how different ... A-LEVEL PHILOSOPHY - 7172 - EXAMPLE STUDENT RESPONSES. AQA Education (AQA) is a registered charity (number 1073334) and a company limited by guarantee registered in ... in the absence of a direct realist response, receive credit. Students should, however, make ...

  13. Summary AQA A Level Philosophy

    Epistemology (7172) Institution. AQA. Book. Philosophy for AS and A Level. Topic summary / notes on direct realism for AQA A Level Philosophy paper 1 epistemology section. These notes were made according to the layout of the specification and were largely helpful as part of my studies for which I received an A* in 2021. Preview 1 out of 4 pages.

  14. direct realism essay plan Flashcards

    a point in favour of direct realism is from Ockham's razor, which states that the best explanation is that which has the most explanatory power and is the simplest, combined with our own account of experience as the direct realist theory aligns with our own common sense view of perception. however, this would not be sufficient to show direct realism is a convincing theory as the objector ...

  15. Direct Realism

    A Level; 5 Pages • Essays / Projects • Year Uploaded: 2023. An essay examining direct realism and its counterarguments, including Russell and Berkeley's perceptual variation, hallucinations, illusions and space-time lag. This document is 30 Exchange Credits. Add to Cart Remove from Cart Proceed to Cart.

  16. Philosophy A level AQA

    Direct realism can still claim that we perceive the sun directly, but as it was moments ago - Illusion: e.g. stick looks crooked in water but isnt in reality - Response: Rational properties: the stick has the mind in dependant rational property of looking crooked to a perceiver looking at it from that perspective.

  17. AQA A level Philosophy Epistemology (Direct Realism, Indirect Realism

    Direct realism is a theory of perception that claims that the world is as it appears to be. Direct realism identifies two elements in perception: the perceiver and the thing perceived. It argues that we perceive mind-independent objects and our senses put us in immediate contact with them.

  18. PDF A-LEVEL PHILOSOPHY 7172/1

    SAMs. 1.0 Mark schemes are prepared by the Lead Assessment Writer and considered, together with the relevant questions, by a panel of subject teachers. This mark scheme includes any amendments made at the standardisation events which all associates participate in and is the scheme which was used by them in this examination.

  19. Direct Realism

    See all Philosophy resources » See all Realism resources » Related discussions on The Student Room. A Level Philosophy 25 marker - please help! » AQA A Level Philosophy Paper 1 7172/1 - 19 May 2022 [Exam Chat] » A-level Philosophy Study Group 2022-2023 » AQA A Level Philosophy Paper 1 + 2 (7172/1+2) 18th and 26th May 2023 [Exam Chat] »

  20. Direct realism A level philosophy Flashcards

    AQA A level philosophy Direct realism Learn with flashcards, games, and more — for free.

  21. Indirect Realism

    An A* grade example answer to a 25 mark question on indirect realism. This document also includes a bullet-point essay plan to help students understand how to structure their essays for maximum marks. After completing your purchase, a download link will be sent to the email address used at checkout.