ScienceDaily

The story of music is the story of humans

Where did music come from recent article discusses how music arose and developed.

How did music begin? Did our early ancestors first start by beating things together to create rhythm, or use their voices to sing? What types of instruments did they use? Has music always been important in human society, and if so, why? These are some of the questions explored in a recent Hypothesis and Theory article published in Frontiers in Sociology . The answers reveal that the story of music is, in many ways, the story of humans.

So, what is music? This is difficult to answer, as everyone has their own idea. "Sound that conveys emotion," is what Jeremy Montagu, of the University of Oxford and author of the article, describes as his. A mother humming or crooning to calm her baby would probably count as music, using this definition, and this simple music probably predated speech.

But where do we draw the line between music and speech? You might think that rhythm, pattern and controlling pitch are important in music, but these things can also apply when someone recites a sonnet or speaks with heightened emotion. Montagu concludes that "each of us in our own way can say 'Yes, this is music', and 'No, that is speech'."

So, when did our ancestors begin making music? If we take singing, then controlling pitch is important. Scientists have studied the fossilized skulls and jaws of early apes, to see if they were able to vocalize and control pitch. About a million years ago, the common ancestor of Neanderthals and modern humans had the vocal anatomy to "sing" like us, but it's impossible to know if they did.

Another important component of music is rhythm. Our early ancestors may have created rhythmic music by clapping their hands. This may be linked to the earliest musical instruments, when somebody realized that smacking stones or sticks together doesn't hurt your hands as much. Many of these instruments are likely to have been made from soft materials like wood or reeds, and so haven't survived. What have survived are bone pipes. Some of the earliest ever found are made from swan and vulture wing bones and are between 39,000 and 43,000 years old. Other ancient instruments have been found in surprising places. For example, there is evidence that people struck stalactites or "rock gongs" in caves dating from 12,000 years ago, with the caves themselves acting as resonators for the sound.

So, we know that music is old, and may have been with us from when humans first evolved. But why did it arise and why has it persisted? There are many possible functions for music. One is dancing. It is unknown if the first dancers created a musical accompaniment, or if music led to people moving rhythmically. Another obvious reason for music is entertainment, which can be personal or communal. Music can also be used for communication, often over large distances, using instruments such as drums or horns. Yet another reason for music is ritual, and virtually every religion uses music.

However, the major reason that music arose and persists may be that it brings people together. "Music leads to bonding, such as bonding between mother and child or bonding between groups," explains Montagu. "Music keeps workers happy when doing repetitive and otherwise boring work, and helps everyone to move together, increasing the force of their work. Dancing or singing together before a hunt or warfare binds participants into a cohesive group." He concludes: "It has even been suggested that music, in causing such bonding, created not only the family but society itself, bringing individuals together who might otherwise have led solitary lives."

  • K-12 Education
  • Language Acquisition
  • Social Psychology
  • Relationships
  • Competition
  • Mammal classification
  • Human skin color
  • Circadian rhythm sleep disorder
  • Circadian rhythm
  • Collaboration

Story Source:

Materials provided by Frontiers . Note: Content may be edited for style and length.

Journal Reference :

  • Jeremy Montagu. How Music and Instruments Began: A Brief Overview of the Origin and Entire Development of Music, from Its Earliest Stages . Frontiers in Sociology , 2017; 2 DOI: 10.3389/fsoc.2017.00008

Cite This Page :

Explore More

  • Heart Disease Risk: More Than One Drink a Day
  • Unlocking Supernova Stardust Secrets
  • Why Do Some Memories Become Longterm?
  • Cell Division Quality Control 'Stopwatch'
  • What Controls Sun's Differential Rotation?
  • Robot, Can You Say 'Cheese'?
  • Researchers Turn Back the Clock On Cancer Cells
  • Making Long-Term Memories: Nerve-Cell Damage
  • A Solar Cell You Can Bend and Soak in Water
  • 'Cosmic Cannibals': Fast-Moving Jets in Space

Trending Topics

Strange & offbeat.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

History of Western Philosophy of Music: Antiquity to 1800

Since its origins in ancient Greece, the Western philosophical tradition has investigated the nature and value of music. This entry examines the development of Western philosophy of music from Greek Antiquity to the end of the eighteenth century. Subsequent developments are covered by the entry on history of western philosophy of music: since 1800 .

Aesthetic concerns remain in the background of Western philosophical thinking on music until the early modern period. Plato and Aristotle are interested in music chiefly because of its educational and political implications, and medieval thinkers typically relate music to metaphysical speculations. This relative neglect of music as an art may be surprising, but it is in line with the late emergence of aesthetics as a branch of philosophy.

Toward the end of the Middle Ages, music theorists begin to pay more attention to the sensuous dimension of music. Subsequent shifts in musical taste prompt questions regarding the origin and value of music’s capacity to express and arouse the emotions.

The eighteenth century develops a system of the arts as the imitation of nature. This raises the issue of how music may fit into such a system. As the instrumental repertoire increases in magnitude and refinement, it becomes clear that an account of music’s position among the arts will require an explanation of pure instrumental music’s meaning and value.

For book-length introductions to the history of Western philosophy of music, see: Fubini 1991; Lippman 1992; Bowman 1998; Martinelli 2012 [2019]; Young forthcoming. Excerpts from classic works are collected in: Strunk 1950; Le Huray and Day 1981; Barker 1990; Lippman 1990; Katz and Dahlhaus 1993; Fubini 1994.

1.1 The Universe as Harmony: Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans

1.2 mathematical and empirical harmonics, 1.3 music, emotions, and society: plato and aristotle, 1.4 aristotelian empirical harmonics: aristoxenus, 1.5 music and moral education: skeptical views, 2.1 early christian views of music: augustine and boethius, 2.2 christian thought and music, 2.3 music among the liberal arts, 2.4 islamic philosophy of music: al-kindi, al-farabi, and ibn sina, 3.1 music and sensory pleasure: tinctoris and zarlino, 3.2 melody and expression: the florentine camerata, 3.3 sense and rationality: mersenne, descartes, leibniz, 3.4 imitation and expression in the eighteenth century, 3.5 the primacy of melody: rousseau, 3.6 music between form and content: kant, other internet resources, related entries, 1. antiquity.

Lippman (1992: chapter 1) observes that Greek Antiquity is responsible for two ideas that shaped Western musical thought until at least the seventeenth century. The first amounts to a metaphysical claim. While details vary greatly, this is the claim that the laws and structure of music correspond to those of the universe. This view is at times supplemented with the additional thought that celestial bodies themselves produce music as they follow their orbits. The Pythagorean concept of cosmic harmony, or harmony of the spheres, is the first known example of the metaphysical conception of music. The second idea is an ethical view, sometimes referred to as ethos theory. According to this view, music has the capacity to alter mood and mold personality, and thus may contribute to moral education (see Lippman 1964: chapter 2).

Some authors, especially those of Pythagorean persuasions, explicitly link the ethical view to the metaphysical one: if the whole universe is musical, so is the human soul, hence music’s power over it. In other authors, such as Aristotle, the ethical and educational value of music is construed as depending mainly on its capacity to imitate or arouse emotions.

No writings survive that are directly attributable to Pythagoras (c. 570–c. 490 BCE). His view of music must therefore be reconstructed from the works of other Pythagoreans, or from more or less sympathetic accounts provided by other authors (a useful collection of texts is found in Barker 1990: chapter 1). Central to Pythagorean philosophy is the notion of harmony as the unity of various parts. In this sense, the concept has a much broader application than to music, for harmony regulates the motion of celestial bodies as well as the human soul (on the concept of harmony in ancient Greek philosophical thought, see Lippman 1964: chapter 1). In the Pythagorean tradition, mathematics is the discipline that investigates harmony. Musical harmony is no exception to this, as the interval of the octave may be expressed as a numerical ratio (2:1). The octave may in turn be considered as the sum of a fifth (3:2) and a fourth (4:3). Pythagoras was generally credited with the discovery of the relations between these intervals. These are best illustrated using a monochord, an instrument constituted by a single string, the vibrating sections of which are determined by the position of a movable bridge. However, it is unclear whether the monochord was in fact used by Pythagoras (Barker 2014: 186), and it is also plausible to assume that instrument makers had some understanding of these relations before they became the object of intellectual speculation.

The series of numbers involved in these ratios (1 to 4, thus adding up to 10) was considered sacred by the Pythagoreans, who named it tetraktys . This metaphysical view of music as a reflection of cosmic order proved to be enormously influential in Western musical thought. As the harmony found in music is essentially the same principle as the one that regulates both the cosmos and the human soul, at least some Pythagoreans thought that their view could explain the effects of music on the listener’s mood and character.

The most notable opponent of the Pythagorean notion of celestial harmony was Aristotle. He offers two main reasons to reject this idea. First, he argues that physical bodies could not be composed of numbers, for the latter have no weight, whereas the former do ( Metaphysics , 14.3). Second, he observes that loud sounds shatter glass and produce a physical effect upon us. The movement of planets in space, Aristotle argues, would produce an even greater effect on us, the absence of which is proof that celestial bodies produce no sound ( On the Heavens , 2.9). In addition to rejecting the idea of a celestial harmony, Aristotle also rejects the related notion that the human soul is a kind of harmony ( On the Soul , 1.4).

‘Harmonics’ is the Ancient Greek discipline that studied musical entities, from intervals to scalar systems (Barker 1990: 3). The Pythagorean tradition marked the start of an influential approach to harmonics, focused on the definition of musical entities in mathematical terms. Early contributors to this approach were Philolaus of Croton (c. 470–c. 385 BCE) and especially Archytas of Tarentum, a contemporary of Plato (Huffman 1993, 2005).

A mathematical treatment of harmonics informed by Pythagorean principles is also given in the Sectio Canonis , a treatise of debated authorship, but often attributed to Euclid. Nicomachus (fl. c. 100 CE) wrote an influential introduction to harmonics from the Pythagorean standpoint (source texts with commentary are collected in Barker 1990; Barker 2007 reconstructs the development of Pythagorean harmonics.)

Parallel to the Pythagorean tradition, an alternative approach sought to ground the laws of music in the way it appears to a competent listener, rather than in explanations from other domains of knowledge. This tradition attempted to provide descriptions of music in autonomously musical terms, and valued accordance with musical practice. This empirical approach to harmonics is in contrast to the mathematical approach adopted by the Pythagorean school (on the differences between the two schools, see Barker 2007 and Barker 1990: 3–8). The contrast between these two schools is of philosophical interest, insofar as it concerns the appropriate level of explanation for aesthetic phenomena. Additionally, mathematical harmonics often were taken to support the metaphysical worldview associated with the Pythagorean doctrine, whereas empirical harmonics tended to follow from an Aristotelian framework (see Barker 2007: chapter 4; Mathiesen 1999: 303).

By far the most important figure in the empirical tradition is that of Aristoxenus (see §1.4 ), although he relied on the work of previous theorists (Barker 2007: chapter 2). The mathematical and empirical traditions are often referred to as Pythagorean and Aristoxenian, respectively.

Theophrastus (c. 371–287 BCE), who followed Aristotle as the head of the Lyceum, is critical of the Pythagorean approach. He observes that we may find quantitative regularities in things other than musical intervals, yet we still consider these things as different from musical entities. This, he argues, must be due to the fact that intervals and melodies are essentially something other than numbers (Barker 1990: 111–114; Lippman 1964: 157–160; Barker 2007: chapter 15).

It is important to stress that the contrast between empirical and mathematical approaches was already evident to ancient theorists and commentators, who often passionately took sides. Ptolemais of Cyrene (fl. between the 3rd century BCE and the 1st century CE), the only known Greek woman music theorist, distinguishes between mousikoi and kanonikoi , a distinction that matches the one between Aristoxenians and Pythagoreans (Barker 2014: 185).

Some theorists developed hybrid views. Ptolemy (c. 100—c. 170 CE) is a case in point, as he explicitly faults both Pythagorean and Aristoxenian approaches ( Harmonics , book I, 2). His philosophical outlook is clearly Pythagorean. For instance, he defends at length the notion of cosmic harmony, tracing parallels between musical and cosmological entities ( Harmonics , book III, 9). However, he attempts to develop mathematical constructs that are better adherent to musical practice than the ones proposed by Pythagoreans, thus addressing a concern characteristic of the Aristoxenian approach.

Aristides Quintilianus (3rd–4th century CE), an author known uniquely for his treatise De Musica , also attempts a fusion of Aristoxenian and Pythagorean elements. While his view of harmonics is indebted to Aristoxenus, his philosophy of music bears a strong Pythagorean influence. Book III of his De Musica illustrates parallels between musical elements and the most disparate parts of reality, from the senses, to virtues, all the way to celestial bodies. Aristides Quintilianus defends the ethical value of music, and in doing so he explicitly refers to Plato’s and Aristotle’s views on the issue. He argues that music imitates moral actions in a way that is superior to that of the other arts, because it achieves mimesis in more than one way, that is, through words and melodic movement ( De Musica , book II, chapter 4). Aristides Quintilianus also classifies musical elements, from modes to instruments, as masculine, feminine, or a mixture of the two (modes are scales that divide up the octave in different sequences of tones and semitones; though the names of Greek modes are identical to the later Church modes, they name different scales). This classification is supposed to help in determining the ethos of musical pieces and instruments, feminine elements being associated with smoothness, and masculine ones with roughness ( De Musica , book II, chapter 12).

A central concern in ancient Greek philosophy of music is the connection between music’s capacity to imitate emotions and its social value. Plato (427/28–347 BCE) and Aristotle (384–322 BCE) both develop an account of this relation, and are particularly interested in the pedagogical consequences of their theories.

When they talk about ‘music’ ( mousikē ), Plato and his contemporaries often have in mind a broader set of art forms than the ones we associate with music today. In this broad sense, mousikē denoted “a seamless complex of instrumental music, poetic word, and co-ordinated physical movement” (Murray & Wilson 2004: 7). Plato sometimes also uses the term in a narrower sense to indicate melodic and rhythmic elements that we would consider today as properly musical (for a brief discussion of the broad and narrow sense of mousikē in Plato, see Schofield 2010: 230–231).

Plato believes that music may contribute to the education of the youth, and more generally to the correct functioning of society, but also holds that it may pose dangers. Underlying Plato’s concerns about the musical education of citizens is the wider assumption that changes in musical taste must be avoided or at least closely scrutinized, as they will produce changes in society ( Republic , 4.424b–d, Laws 2.660a-b). In the Laws , Plato goes so far as to describe the changes in musical taste that followed the Persian wars as the trigger for subsequent rejection of authority and societal unrest ( Laws , 700a-701b).

According to Plato, the sensible world is an imperfect copy of perfect and immutable ideas. Plato’s general view of the arts, including music, is that they are an imitation ( mimesis ) of objects found in the sensible world. This leads to his famous condemnation of art in Book X of his Republic . For, if our world is already a copy, then the arts provide us with copies of a copy. Thus, Plato’s metaphysics motivates his dismissive view of art’s epistemic value.

However, Plato also holds that the musical imitation of some human emotions may be ethically beneficial, especially at the stage when children are too young to be responsive to ethical education that relies on a discursive and rational basis. Plato first describes the emotions in question indirectly, one as the emotion of a person who is steadfast and resolute in misfortune or while fighting, the other as the state of “someone engaged in a peaceful, unforced, voluntary action” ( Republic , 3.399b). Plato holds that these emotions, which he then refers to explicitly as courage and moderation, are best imitated through the Dorian and Phrygian modes, which

imitate the violent or voluntary tones of voice of those who are moderate and courageous, whether in good fortune or in bad. ( Republic , 3.399c)

Thus, Plato construes musical imitation of emotions as grounded on the resemblance of music to human expressive behavior, particularly vocal. At least on one occasion, he also seems to hold that music imitates the bodily movements associated with emotions ( Laws , 2.654e-655a). This could be considered the first defense of the idea that musical expressiveness is due to the music’s resemblance to human expressive behavior, a position that remains popular to this day (see the entry on href="../hist-westphilmusicsince-1800/#AnalPhilMusi" history of western philosophy of music: since 1800, section 2.6 ).

How does the musical imitation of courage and moderation achieve its educational purpose? At least some passages suggest that Plato thought music to be capable of influencing human character in virtue of the common harmonic nature shared by the soul, music, and the universe. For instance, in the Republic , Socrates tells Glaucon that

rhythm and harmony permeate the inner part of the soul more than anything else, affecting it most strongly and bringing it grace, so that if someone is properly educated in music and poetry, it makes him graceful, but if not, then the opposite. ( Republic , 3.401d; see also Republic , 3.412a, Timaeus , 47d-e, and Laches , 188d)

Young (forthcoming) observes that Plato seems elsewhere to reject the Pythagorean view of the soul as harmony ( Phaedo , 89–95). On this basis, Young holds that Plato’s view of the ethical benefits of music is best interpreted as simply relying on the music’s imitative capacity. Regardless of what one makes of Plato’s view of the soul as harmony, it is clear that he was influenced by the Pythagorean view of the universe as governed by harmony, especially in the Timaeus .

On the surface, Aristotle’s view may appear close to Plato’s. Both philosophers hold music’s value to reside in its imitation of emotions. However, Aristotle’s view is considerably more nuanced.

In the Poetics (1447a), Aristotle makes clear that all the arts are imitative, although they differ in the means, object, and manner of imitation. Aristotle has a more positive view of imitation than Plato, observing that humans are prone to it since childhood, and granting that we may learn through imitation. This cognitive value of imitations also explains why we feel pleasure when engaging with them, even when they imitate things we would find ugly or repulsive in real life ( Poetics , 1448b 5–20).

Discussing the object of musical imitations, Aristotle introduces an interesting distinction between mere indications or signs ( sēmeia ) of emotional states and the states themselves. Signs of emotional states are the observable behavior that accompanies the occurrence of such states. Aristotle holds that the visual arts merely imitate signs of emotions. For instance, a painter may represent a man weeping or smiling. However, music is able to imitate the emotional states themselves. A plausible reading of Aristotle’s view is that he regarded music as capable of arousing the emotions it imitates, and that this capacity ultimately explains how music may imitate emotional states themselves, as opposed to their manifestations. On this analysis, the object of musical imitation cannot be specified separately from the emotional response the music arouses in the listener (Halliwell (2002: 248) stresses this point; Sörbom 1994 offers an alternative interpretation).

To understand the relation between Aristotle’s view of musical imitation and its educational role, it is useful to examine this passage:

Besides, when men hear imitations, even apart from the rhythms and tunes themselves, their feelings move in sympathy. Since then music is a pleasure, and excellence consists in rejoicing and loving and hating rightly, there is clearly nothing which we are so much concerned to acquire and to cultivate as the power of forming right judgments, and of taking delight in good dispositions and noble actions. ( Politics , 1340a)

Here Aristotle seems to be arguing the following: music imitates character, that is, various dispositions and emotional states; the musical imitation of such states generates pleasure in the listener; so, if we restrict musical imitations to those of morally praiseworthy states, listeners will be pleased at such states in real life. Aristotle is relying on the assumption that the pleasure accompanying our engagement with an imitation will extend to the experience of the imitated object in real life. As he expresses it:

The habit of feeling pleasure or pain at mere representations is not far removed from the same feeling about realities. ( Politics , 1340a)

Therefore, the moral value of musical education depends on the capacity of mimetic representations to induce pleasure in those who appreciate them. While this capacity may be shared by both music and the visual arts, it is only music, according to Aristotle, that is able represent states of character, as opposed to merely representing their manifestations.

An additional function of music, according to Aristotle, is catharsis. Music may help individuals who are in states of extreme enthusiasm, pity, or fear return to a more balanced state ( Politics , 1342a). The details of this process are hard to reconstruct, because they are tied to the debated concept of catharsis, introduced by Aristotle in his definition of tragedy ( Poetics , 1449b). It seems clear that Aristotle thought of the cathartic process as requiring music expressive of emotions akin to the ones to be purged. For example, a state of uncontrolled religious frenzy could be subdued by means of frenzied music.

Plato and Aristotle come apart also with regard to the role of the pleasure we take in listening to music. Plato’s approach is a pragmatic one. The aspects of music he values are all and only those that contribute to its ethical role. Such a principle governs Plato’s observations on musical pleasure. He does not deny that music may be able to induce pleasure. However, this pleasure is only valuable insofar as it attracts listeners to music that is good for their moral education ( Laws , 2.668a-b).

Plato also notes that pleasurable responses may become associated with music of the morally questionable sort, as such responses depend also on habituation ( Laws , 7.802c-d). From this he concludes that it is of great importance to control children’s musical environment.

Aristotle’s view of musical pleasure is far more positive. It is clear from the above that pleasure plays a role in Aristotle’s account of music’s educational value. But Aristotle also thinks that pleasure generated by music is valuable for two other reasons. First, music may provide relaxation to those that are tired from work. In this sense, the pleasure it produces is similar to that produced by eating or sleeping ( Politics , 1339a-b). Second, and perhaps more interestingly, Aristotle holds that the pleasure of music should be part of a cultivated life ( Politics , 1339b; for a discussion of the functions of music in Aristotle, see Lippman 1964: 130–131.)

Both Plato and Aristotle comment on the value of instrumental music. Plato’s pragmatic attitude grounds his injunction against complexity and subtlety in music ( Republic , 3.399c-e). He holds that music should have a vocal part, and argues that the musical elements should conform to the emotional state described by the piece’s lyrical content ( Republic , 3.400d). This concern with clear and unequivocal musical imitation also motivates Plato’s stance on the value of instrumental music. While it is clear that Plato holds the purely musical elements of melody and rhythm to have an imitative potential, he attributes little value to instrumental music, presumably because he believes that it is unable to provide an unequivocal imitation of courage and moderation ( Laws 2.669 d-e).

Aristotle is again more nuanced. According to him, both vocal and instrumental music produce pleasure ( Politics , 1339b). In general, despite his reservations concerning the aulos (an instrument comprising two, linked, reed pipes) ( Politics , 1341a), Aristotle’s attitude toward instrumental music is far less critical than Plato’s. For example, Aristotle is clear in conceding that even purely instrumental music can arouse distinct emotions, due to both its melodic and rhythmic elements ( Politics , 1340a-b).

A disciple of Aristotle, Aristoxenus (fl. 4th century BCE) argues that harmonics should not be concerned with an explanation of musical phenomena in mathematical terms, but rather describe musical structures through the analysis of musical elements as objects of perception. For example, Aristoxenus distinguishes between the speaking and singing voice, the former being characterized by a continuous movement across pitch space, the latter by intervallic movement from one pitch to another ( Elementa Harmonica , book I, 9–10). On the basis of this distinction, he provides a definition of note ( phthongos ) as any pitch on which the voice rests and that has a position in a given melodic line ( Elementa Harmonica , book I, 9–10; for a detailed discussion of Aristoxenus as a music theorist, see Mathiesen 1999: 294–344).

Another striking element in Aristoxenus’ conception is his view of musical understanding, which he thinks involves the faculties of perception and memory,

for we have to perceive what is coming to be and remember what has come to be. There is no other way of following the contents of music. ( Elementa Harmonica , book II, 38–39)

Note that perception is not described as the mere awareness of what is present to our senses at a given time, but includes an anticipation of “what is coming to be”. Here, Aristoxenus seems to anticipate an account of musical understanding similar to the one recently defended by Jerrold Levinson (1997).

Aristoxenus’ view of the moral effects of music is harder to reconstruct. While it is clear that he thought music to be a proper object of ethical evaluation, he likely had a less dogmatic conception of the link between given modes and their moral value than Aristotle (see Rocconi 2012 and Barker 2007: 245 ff.).

Some ancient philosophers reject the view that music is valuable beyond the pleasurable experience it affords. In doing so, they question the educational value of music.

In his De Musica , the epicurean Philodemus (c. 110–c. 30 BCE) rejects the widespread view that music may imitate the passions, claiming that music is no better able to represent psychological states than the art of cooking (see Wilkinson 1938). Philodemus appeals to Democritus (c. 460–c. 370 BCE), but evidence regarding the latter’s views is scant. While it is clear that Democritus held music to stand lower than other arts in terms of utility, it is probably not true that he thought this deprived it of educational value (see Brancacci 2007: 193–95).

Sextus Empiricus (fl. 3rd century CE), in Against the Musicians , also denies that music could have any positive educational role. While he concedes that we may enjoy music, he denies that the study of music could contribute to such enjoyment. In support of this, he also compares music to cookery, arguing that in both cases enjoyment is independent of our understanding of the thing enjoyed ( Against the Musicians , 24–25).

2. Late Antiquity and the Middle Ages

Despite spanning about one thousand years, the period that goes from late Antiquity to the end of the Middle Ages brought little new to Western philosophy of music.

A prominent feature of this period is the emergence of the Christian worldview. Christian thinking on music adapts some of the views it had inherited from Greek Antiquity, chief among them the Pythagorean harmony of the spheres and the idea that music may influence character.

The medieval approach to music is biased toward the point of view of the theoretician. Music is typically grouped together with scientific disciplines. The sensory pleasure of the listener is rarely remarked upon, and at times considered with suspicion. The individuality and creativity of the composer is also neglected, and the role of performing musicians almost entirely ignored or dismissed (Schuller 1988, and Young forthcoming (chapter 2) are extensive introductions to medieval musical aesthetics).

Saint Augustine of Hippo (354–430), philosopher and Father of the Church, devoted to music his treatise De Musica . Although mostly technical in character, the book is an early statement of the medieval view of music as first and foremost a science, rather than a practical occupation. Augustine defines music as “the science of mensurating well” ( scientia bene modulandi —this last word is at times rendered as ‘modulation’), that is, the discipline concerned with the attainment of measure and proportion ( De Musica , book I, 2).

An almost identical definition of music is found in Cassiodorus (485–c. 585) who states that “Music indeed is the knowledge of apt modulation” ( Institutiones , 5), as well as in Isidore of Seville’s (560–636) Etymologiarum :

Music is an art of modulation consisting of tone and song called music by derivation from the Muses. ( Etymologiarum , book III, 15)

Augustine’s attitude toward the sensory pleasure derived from music was conflicted. On the one hand, he recognizes music’s power in worship. On the other hand, he is aware that this could also lead the faithful to stray away from the religious content of the experience ( Confessions , II).

The philosopher Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius (c. 480–525/26), normally referred to simply as Boethius, had a fundamental role in shaping medieval musical thinking. Through commentated translations of Greek authors and original expositions of their views, Boethius allowed classical Greek philosophical ideas to survive into the Middle Ages. He did so in the field of music by writing De Institutione Musica . In this work, Boethius summarizes music theory as found in the Greek treatises he knew. The book also distinguishes between three types of music: musica mundana , humana , and instrumentalis . Musica mundana is the harmony of the cosmos, a Pythagorean concept that found widespread acceptance over the course of the Middle Ages, though it was recast in Christian terms. Musica humana is described only briefly by Boethius, though it is clear that it is the harmony between the various elements that compose the human body. Some modern accounts of Boethius’s thought identify musica humana with singing, but this is incorrect, though it is true that later medieval thinkers used the term in such a way (see Dyer 2007: 59; 64; 69). Finally, musica instrumentalis is sounding music, vocal and instrumental. While this is undoubtedly regarded today as the core of music, Boethius considers it as music only in a derivative sense. Boethius’s tripartite division is repeated and accepted by numerous medieval writers on music.

Boethius also takes from Greek Antiquity the Platonic view that music may arouse emotions and influence human character. He observes that this sets music apart from other mathematical disciplines ( De Institutione Musica , book I, 1).

The impact of Christianity on medieval musical thinking is evident in the religious interpretation given of two philosophical views from Antiquity, the harmony of the spheres and the ethos theory, according to which music may shape the listener’s character. Both of these ideas were held by Boethius (see the preceding section) and found widespread acceptance among medieval writers.

The Christian take on the harmony of the spheres consists in the claim that such harmony was imposed on the universe by the Creator. The beauty of music, including sounding music, is thus traced back to music’s partaking in that divine harmony. John Scottus Eriugena (c. 800–c. 877) expresses such a view in his Periphyseon , as evident from his very definition of music:

Music is the art which by the light of reason studies the harmony of all things that are in motion that is knowable by natural proportions. ( Periphyseon , 475B)

That the harmony of the spheres could be interpreted in Christian terms did not prevent philosophers from rejecting it, especially once Aristotle’s works had become available. Albert the Great (Albertus Magnus) (c. 1200–1280) is an example of a prominent philosopher who rejects the idea of a celestial harmony. Appealing to arguments based on the structure of the cosmos, he discards the idea that the movement of celestial bodies could produce harmonious sounds ( Liber de Causis Proprietatum Elementorum , book II, 2.1; on the harmony of the spheres in the thirteenth century, see Mews 2011).

The idea that music may influence character was widely accepted over the course of the Middle Ages. It was supported by the exaggerated accounts of music’s powers that had survived from Antiquity. The medieval Christian version of the ethos theory normally stresses the devotional potential of music.

Following Martianus Capella’s (fl. c. 410) The Marriage of Philology and Mercury , medieval thinkers classified music as one of the liberal arts. These were divided into the arts of the trivium (grammar, logic and rhetoric) and the quadrivium (arithmetic, geometry, astronomy and music). The arts of the trivium were referred to as artes sermocinales , because they are related to discourse and language. The arts of the quadrivium were instead the artes reales , studying the mathematical and physical constitution of the universe. The classification of music as one of the artes reales is unsurprising in light of the Pythagorean-Boethian view of music as primarily concerned with proportions and harmony.

While this classification remained mostly unchallenged, there were some important dissenting voices (for an overview, see Dyer 2007). These disputes regarding the proper classification of music are important because they reflect underlying concerns with music’s nature and purposes. From the thirteenth century onwards, theorists and philosophers became more concerned with the practical and acoustic sides of music-making, and less with its theological implications. For instance, the English grammarian John of Garland (1195–1272) distinguishes between plainsong, mensural music, and instrumental music, and does so on the bases of historical and musicological differences between such repertoires (see Fubini 1991: 94).

The progressive assimilation of Aristotle’s work in medieval thought meant that the physical, sounding aspects of music began to be considered as important as its mathematical ones. Evidence of this is Thomas Aquinas’s classification of music as one of the scientie medie , that is, disciplines that apply mathematics to the study of natural objects (see Dyer 2007: 67–68).

As observed by Young (forthcoming: chapter 2), it is appropriate to include medieval Islamic philosophy in a survey of Western musical thinking, as Islamic philosophers relied largely on the same Greek authors that were central to the European tradition. In fact, translations of Greek works were more widely available in the Islamic world. Partly because of their earlier contact with Aristotle’s philosophy, Islamic philosophers are more inclined to value the sensory character of music and to accept it as an object of aesthetic appreciation.

The philosopher al-Kindi (c. 800–870) holds a broadly Pythagorean view of music (see Shehadi 1995: chapter 1, and Adamson 2007: 172–180). According to him, a relationship of affinity holds between musical elements and parts of the cosmos. This affinity allows Kindi to trace correspondences between musical elements and the extra-musical world. Kindi’s acceptance of Pythagorean views is also exemplified by his claim that music exercises a power of the human body in virtue of the affinity between its constitution and that of various musical instruments.

Al-Farabi (872–950) is a notable representative of the Aristotelian current in medieval Islamic philosophy of music (see Shehadi 1995: chapter 3). Farabi rejects the harmony of the spheres. Rather than speculating about music’s origin in the structure of the cosmos, he attempts to understand it as a human phenomenon, suggesting that vocal music may have developed out of necessities such as the expression of pleasant and unpleasant states. Farabi also distinguishes three types of melody, according to the effect it produces in the listener. Some melodies are pleasing to the ear, others evoke images, and yet others express psychological states. It is possible for a melody to do more than one of these things, and in fact Farabi holds that the best melodies tend to have all three such effects.

Ibn Sina, known in the West as Avicenna (980–1037) describes music as a mathematical science, but argues that a theory of music should be primarily concerned with the explanation of music as heard. This emphasis on the appropriate level of explanation is reminiscent of Aristoxenus (see §1.4 ), who exercised a clear influence on Islamic philosophy of music. Ibn Sina also revives the Aristotelian view that music may imitate human character and psychological states (on Ibn Sina’s philosophy of music, see Shehadi 1995: chapter 4).

3. Early Modern Period

From the fifteenth century, writers on music begin to elaborate on the aesthetic aspects of musical experience. The theorist and composer Johannes Tinctoris (c. 1435–1511) exemplifies various aspects of this new outlook on music. He defines harmony and consonance in terms of their appearance to the listener, rather than through mathematical notions. Harmony is thus described as the pleasing effect produced by sounds, whereas consonance and dissonance are respectively characterized as combinations of sounds that bring sweetness to the ear or hurt it ( Liber de arte contrapuncti , chapter 2). In his Complexus effectuum musices , Tinctoris lists prominent effects of music, most of which involve emotional arousal, while the dedication of his Proportionale Musices refers back to Antiquity and the alleged emotional potency of its music.

Tinctoris thus prefigures two tendencies typical of early modern thinking about music: first, the focus on the subjective experience of music, and on the feelings of pleasure and displeasure that accompany it; second, the value attributed to music’s expressive power, and the related idea that ancient music’s capacity to arouse emotions was greater than that of the music of their time.

The first of these tendencies is also embodied in the work of Gioseffo Zarlino (1517–1590). A towering figure in Western music theory, Zarlino is normally considered as the theorist who initiated the move away from medieval modality and toward tonal harmony. According to Zarlino, rules of composition are good insofar as they produce beautiful music, whose purpose is to “improve” and “delight” (Zarlino 1558: book III, 71). However, Zarlino does not reject the role of rationality, and especially of mathematics, because its laws ultimately underlie the senses of sight and hearing (Zarlino 1588: 34–36).

In Book II of his Dodecachordon (1547), the humanist Heinrich Glarean (also known as Glareanus) (1488–1563) argues that composers of polyphonic music are inferior to those who set a single melodic line to a text. He speculates that the latter was the way Greeks, Romans, and early Christian communities composed music. Monody is superior on the grounds that it requires an exercise in invention, whereas the polyphonist merely borrows a melodic line and then carries out a task that is predominantly intellectual. According to Glareanus, monody has a natural character and an expressive immediacy that is lost in subsequent development. Less than half a century later, both the reference to a classical model and the vindication of monody became crucially important in Italian musical thinking and practice. Toward the end of the sixteenth century, a group of Florentine intellectuals and musicians gathered around the figure of Giovanni de’ Bardi, a nobleman and amateur musician. This group is normally referred to as the Florentine Camerata, or Camerata de’ Bardi. Its goal was to recover the expressive potential of music, as described in ancient Greek and Roman sources. Music’s power to arouse emotions was thought to have been lost during the Middle Ages, as polyphony developed. The envisaged solution was a return to monody, and more precisely to a melodic line that would follow and emphasize the prosodic features of impassioned speech (Palisca 2006: chapter 7; Palisca 1989 is an influential collection of source readings). Thus, the main goal of the Camerata seems to have been expression, to be intended here as the arousal of emotion, while the imitation of speech prosody was considered a means to that end. This is philosophically significant in that it indicates a revival of the classical Greek idea that music is expressive in virtue of its resemblance to the way human beings express their emotions (see §1.3 ).

This resulted in the birth of the so-called stile rappresentativo , the vocal style characteristic of early opera, of which Claudio Monteverdi’s (1567–1643) L’Orfeo (1607) is considered the first masterpiece. Giulio Caccini (1550–1618) and Jacopo Peri (1561–1633) were active members of the Camerata, and have both left explicit discussion of the theories that informed their musical style (relevant textual excerpts are collected in Strunk 1950: 370–392).

While Monteverdi may be considered the most representative musician associated with this turn to melody and expression, the Camerata’s most significant theoretical figure was Vincenzo Galilei (c. 1520–1591), an accomplished composer and lutenist, father of the astronomer Galileo. In his Dialogue of Ancient and Modern Music (1581), Galilei takes issue with contemporary practices, particularly with counterpoint. He concedes that the polyphonic music of his time is a source of aural pleasure, but faults it for its incapacity to move the listener,

[f]or its sole aim is to delight the ear, while that of ancient music is to induce in another the same passion that one feels oneself. (Galilei 1581 [1950: 317])

Both Monteverdi and Galilei faced the reaction of more conservative figures. Giovanni Maria Artusi (c. 1540–1613), in L’Artusi or Of the Imperfections of Modern Music (1600), attacks the work of an unnamed composer, though it is apparent that he has in mind composers such as Monteverdi and Carlo Gesualdo (1566–1613). Artusi concedes that the newly developed monodic style is expressive, but denies that expression is worth the sacrifice of compositional rules that are dictated by reason. The dispute between Artusi and Monteverdi crystallized the clash between the so-called prima and seconda prattica , the former indicating the old polyphonic style, the latter the new preference for accompanied monody.

Galilei faced criticism from his former teacher Zarlino. In his Sopplimenti musicali (1588), Zarlino argues that the imitation of impassioned speech belongs to the art of rhetoric or to declaimed poetry, not music. Musicians should confine themselves to the imitation of the text’s content, rather than to its possible delivery, and they should do so through the choice of appropriate harmonies (Zarlino 1588: 316–318). Zarlino’s reservations about expressive melody are of particular importance, as they may be seen as the first manifestation of a recurring contrast between two opposite tendencies, epitomized by the clash between Rousseau and Rameau (see §3.5 ). Whereas one strand locates music’s chief source of expression in melody, the other defends the primacy of harmony, often downplaying the role of possible resemblances between melodic contour and human expressive behavior (Young, forthcoming, names the two tendencies empiricism and rationalism , respectively, following their development and occasional overlap).

Despite their disagreements, both approaches valued expression in music set to a text. A full vindication of the expressive power of instrumental music was not among the programmatic goals of either the Camerata or of those who, like Zarlino, stress the importance of harmonic elements. Caccini is critical of music that obscures the text, because

such music and musicians gave no other delight than what harmony could give the ear, for, unless the words were understood, they could not move the understanding. (Caccini 1600 [1950: 378])

Zarlino, following Plato, claims that melody and harmony should be suitable to the text, and cashes out this suitability in terms of similarity:

we must also make a choice of a harmony and a rhythm similar to the nature of the matters contained in the speech in order that from the combination of these things, put together with proportion, may result a melody suited to the purpose. (Zarlino 1558: book IV, 32 [1950: 256])

Moreover, these authors unanimously hold that it is the music that has to be adapted to a text, rather than the other way around. In the foreword to Monteverdi’s Scherzi Musicali (1607), his brother Giulio Cesare claims that Claudio’s goal was “to make the words the mistress of the harmony and not the servant” (Monteverdi 1607 [1950: 406]).

While this stress on the priority of the text was the product of a renewed interest in emotional expression in vocal music, Church authorities also became concerned with the confused polyphonic styles and the way they obfuscated liturgical content, and thus they also promoted textural clarity in polyphonic music (see Fellerer 1953).

While it is important to note that the early modern period mitigated the medieval insistence on a mathematical treatment of music with an approach that paid greater attention to its sensory appearance, it would be incorrect to say that the search for mathematical regularities was altogether abandoned. On the one hand, the budding scientific outlook favored the extension of the experimental method to the realm of sound, an operation that obviously included mathematical modeling. Thus, rather than giving up on mathematical descriptions of music altogether, early modern theorists abandoned the abstract framework in which these descriptions had been formulated. On the other hand, accounts of music in mathematical terms continued to survive in the metaphysical speculations of music theorists and philosophers.

Exemplary of these tendencies is the French mathematician Marin Mersenne (1588–1648), who was interested in a number of questions connected to the mathematical nature of music. While he understood the importance of empirical verification, Mersenne was also convinced of a fundamental harmony between the mathematical order of music and that of the whole cosmos, as evident from the title of his most important work, Harmonie Universelle (1636).

A particularly interesting theme in this sprawling treatise is the contrast between the rational structure of music and its sensuous appearance, best illustrated through Mersenne’s discussion of consonance. Having defined consonance in terms of coincidence in air vibrations, Mersenne had to explain why consonance and sensory agreeableness do not always go hand in hand. For instance, the major third is more agreeable than the fourth, although this is more consonant. Mersenne had an interesting correspondence with Descartes on the matter, in which the former manifests his wish to provide a definition of agreeableness that is as objective as that of consonance, while the latter expresses skepticism about the project, and claims that agreeableness is dependent on variation in taste, as well as in musical context (see Jorgensen 2012).

Early in his life, René Descartes (1596–1650) devoted a treatise to music, the Compendium Musicae (written in 1618 and published posthumously in 1650). This work is dominated by scientific concerns rather than philosophical ones, but the very start of the treatise is characteristic of its age, as Descartes states that music’s goal is “to please and to arouse various Affections in us” (Descartes 1650). But Descartes’s most important impact on philosophy of music is actually due to his treatise on emotions, The Passions of the Soul (1649). In this work, Descartes defines emotions as the result of the action produced by external objects on the animal spirits, a thin air-like substance that stirs our passions whenever it is set in motion. Descartes also distinguishes six basic emotions: wonder, love, hatred, desire, joy, and sadness.

This taxonomy of emotions and the mechanistic description of their functioning will prove important to the so-called Affektenlehre , or doctrine of the affections, the eighteenth century view that a piece of music should arouse a specific emotion in the listener. Affektenlehre theorists believed that this goal could be achieved through the use of specific musical devices, each associated with a given emotion. The German composer Johann Mattheson may be considered the most prominent representative of this tradition. He explicitly endorses Descartes’ theory of emotions in his treatise Der vollkommene Capellmeister (Mattheson 1739: I, iii, §51).

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716), philosopher and mathematician, devoted to music only scattered observations. Yet, his view of music’s value is of particular interest, as it is indicative of the attempt to reconcile rational and sensuous elements in our appreciation of music (see Fubini 1991: 149). Leibniz accepts that the main goal of music is to move us. In fact, he notes that, while music is obviously so apt to do so, “this main purpose is not usually sufficiently noticed or sought after” (Leibniz, On Wisdom ). However, Leibniz also specifies that this sensuous pleasure is the result of the automatic and unconscious apprehension through music of the rational structure of the universe. He writes:

Music charms us, although its beauty consists only in the agreement of numbers and in the counting, which we do not perceive but which the soul nevertheless continues to carry out, of the beats or vibrations of sounding bodies which coincide at certain intervals. (Leibniz 1714: 614)

Two related questions may be asked with regard to imitation in music. The first is whether music may imitate extra-musical objects, and what value this imitation may have. The second concerns the role of such imitation in the musical expression of emotions. Over the course of the eighteenth century, answers to both questions were characterized by a growing skepticism toward imitation (see Lippman 1992: chapter 6). The gradual rise of instrumental music was certainly partly responsible for this change in attitude. Its increasing formal, melodic, and harmonic complexity made it less plausible to argue that it imitated the speaking voice, and yet this complexity only heightened music’s power to express and arouse the emotions.

A natural way out of this impasse is to explicitly define expression in terms of emotional arousal, distinguishing it from the mere musical depiction of worldly objects, including the external manifestations of human emotions. This is the option taken by Charles Avison (1709–1770) in his Essay on Musical Expression , first published in 1752. Avison distinguishes between music resembling extra-musical objects, including manifestations of emotions, such as laughter, and music that is able to provoke an emotional response in the listener. The former case is musical ‘imitation’, which Avison claims produces “a reflex act of the understanding” (Avison 1775: 50), while the latter is ‘expression’. Avison argues that the goal of music is to pursue expression, which is achieved by the competent use of melody and harmony. While the idea that music is valuable because it moves the listener was not new, Avison’s clarity in decoupling it from imitation is noteworthy.

However, other theorists were not as explicit and careful as Avison with their terminology, nor as ready to jettison imitation, which the eighteenth century considered essential to the fine arts. Moreover, it had been customary since the Camerata’s time to construe expression as dependent on imitation (see Palisca 2006: chapter 10). Thus, a number of authors adopted conservative positions, defending a qualified concept of musical imitation, or simply accepting that music’s imitative capacities are limited. In the second half of the century, imitation gradually took on a more peripheral role, and philosophers started to focus on alternative sources of value for music as an art, from formal structure to emotional arousal.

This gradual rejection of the idea of music as an imitative art is perhaps best manifested in France. This might seem puzzling, as the eighteenth century view of imitation as the hallmark of fine arts found its most famous expression in The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle (1746), by Charles Batteux (1713–1780). In this work, Batteux defines art as the imitation of beautiful nature ( belle nature ). Different arts imitate different parts of nature. Music imitates the human expression of emotions. It is interesting to note that Batteux repeatedly states that music expresses the emotions, as opposed to imitating them, although the discrepancy seems to be merely terminological. Batteux can conceive of music that fails to be imitative, but does not consider it valuable:

It would be like a chromatic harpsichord that offers us colours and series of colours. It would amuse the eyes, perhaps, but bore the mind. (Batteux 1746: part III, section III, chapter 2)

Earlier than Batteux, Jean-Baptiste Du Bos (1670–1742) had similarly construed music as an imitative art in his Critical Reflections on Poetry and Painting (1719). Du Bos attempts to show that, in vocal music, melody, harmony, and rhythm all contribute to the imitation of impassioned speech. Instrumental music imitates natural sounds instead. While he recognizes that music may charm the senses, Du Bos thinks that the only valuable response to music is the one that comes from its appreciation as an imitation. Music may still please without imitating, but it is only when it imitates that it really moves. Consequently, Du Bos condemns music that fails to be imitative.

The Encyclopedists Jean Le Rond D’Alembert (1717–1783) and Didier Diderot (1713–1784) also hold onto the idea that music is essentially imitative. D’Alembert states that

[t]he composers of instrumental music will make nothing but an empty noise as long as they do not have in their heads […] an action or an expression to be represented. (D’Alembert 1759: XXXVIII)

In the dialogue Rameau’s Nephew (1760), Diderot claims that

[s]ong is an imitation of physical noises or of the accents of the passions, through the sounds of a scale invented by art or inspired by nature, whichever you please, either with the voice or with an instrument. (Diderot 1760: 104ndash;5)

Musical imitation is also defended by Jean-Jacques Rousseau, but in an importantly qualified version (see the following section).

From the 1770s onwards, the view of music as an imitative art appears increasingly untenable, and the idea that music is expressive of the emotions because it imitates human expressive behavior also comes under attack. This new trend is evident in works such as André Morellet’s (1727–1819) Of Expression in Music and Imitation in the Arts (1771), as well as Musical Expression Placed Among the Chimeras (1779). This latter work was written by Boyé, whose biographical details are unknown. Boyé’s treatise pairs the rejection of imitation with the claim that melody and harmony are worthy of appreciation in themselves:

The principal object of music is to please us physically, without the mind putting itself to the trouble of searching for useless comparisons to it. (quoted in Lippman 1992: 95)

The composer and theorist Michel-Paul Guy de Chabanon (1730–1792) is arguably the most representative and radical example of the new skeptical mentality. In his Observations on Music and Principally on the Metaphysics of Art (1779), Chabanon offers a variety of arguments against the idea that the musical expression of emotions depends on the imitation of their vocal manifestations. Children respond emotionally to music, he observes, yet they cannot appreciate musical imitation. The same is true of individuals who are unfamiliar with the Western musical tradition. Moreover, imitation is insufficient for expression. For example, laughter is naturally associated with gaiety, but a musical imitation of laughter would fail to result in gay music. Thus, music may express emotions without imitating their external manifestations. Conversely, Chabanon observes that music may express emotions that do not have any typical manifestation:

Many of our passions have no particular cry associated with them, and yet music may express them. (Chabanon 1779: VIII)

In addition to the already mentioned Avison, other English writers questioned the role of imitation in music (see Schueller 1948). Francis Hutcheson (1694–1746), in An Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design (1725), distinguishes between original and comparative beauty, the former being judged independently of any comparison, with the latter depending instead on imitation. According to Hutcheson, music is an example of original beauty, although its melodic element also allows for comparative beauty, in that it may resemble impassioned speech. In detecting this resemblance,

we shall be touched by it in a very sensible manner, and have melancholy, joy, gravity, thoughtfulness excited in us by a sort of sympathy or contagion . (Hutcheson 1725: section VI, XII)

This passage is significant because it gives a clear account of how music may express an emotion (through the imitation of its characteristic vocal expression), while at the same time arousing it in the listener.

In his Observations on the Correspondence between Poetry and Music (1769), the Irish writer Daniel Webb (1719–1798) explains the emotional effects of music by appealing to a physiological theory of emotions similar to Descartes’s. According to this view, music may give us impressions , that is, it may put us in a state of mind, which may be further specified by accompanying words. In comparing music with painting and sculpture, Webb notes that the latter may act on our emotions only through their imitations, that is, their represented content, whereas music may do so through both imitations and impressions (Webb 1769: 28). In this way, Webb acknowledges that the expressive potential of music is greater than that of the visual arts, and that this privileged position is not due to imitation.

James Beattie (1735–1803), a Scottish philosopher, voices concerns similar to those of Chabanon when he observes that there are emotions that music may express, that do not have a typical vocal manifestation. On the basis of this, he rejects the view that music is of necessity imitative, though he concedes that it may be. More significantly, Beattie claims that there is a crucial difference between music and the paradigmatically imitative art of painting. While good paintings are of necessity good imitations, and bad paintings are necessarily bad ones, good and bad works of music may be either good or bad imitations (Beattie 1779: part I, chapter VI, section 1).

The Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid (1710–1796) argues that perception presents us with sensations, which function as signs of objective qualities. Some sensations are artificial signs, instituted by human agreement. Such are words—the connection between ‘cat’ and the animal sitting on my lap being arbitrary. Other sensations are natural signs, and function independently of human agency—for instance, the connection between smoke and fire. Natural signs typically require us to learn their connection to the signified objective quality, as in the case of smoke and fire. However, in some cases a natural sign signifies without requiring prior experience—a child can detect the anger in an angry face and responds to it immediately. Musical expression is explicitly described by Reid as an example of this category:

One kind of music inspires grief, another love, another rage or fury. These are all material representations of some affection of the mind. None of these are gained by experience. ( Lectures on the Fine Arts , “Mind and Body”)

Thus, musical expression “is nothing but the fitness of certain sounds to produce certain sentiments in our minds” ( Lectures on the Fine Arts , “Taste and the Fine Arts”). As for the imitation of birdsong, battles, and the like, Reid maintains that these only marginally contribute to the beauty of music. The importance of Reid’s view resides in his philosophically grounded view of expression, which does not involve imitation at all.

The economist and philosopher Adam Smith (1723–90) traces a sharp distinction between vocal and instrumental music. He holds that the greater the disparity between medium and imitated object, the more pleasure an imitative art will occasion ( Of the Nature of that Imitation that Takes Place in what are called The Imitative Arts , part I, 6–7). Vocal music may thus only slightly resemble impassioned speech, but precisely because of this it will delight us when it successfully imitates it ( Of the Nature of that Imitation , part II, 12). Instrumental music, however, lacking a text and deprived of vocal articulation, cannot imitate any object successfully, as we can hardly ever recognize anything in it unless prompted by a description ( Of the Nature of that Imitation , part II, 17). Smith develops an alternative view of musical expression, which he illustrates with an interesting parallel. Just as a natural landscape may be gloomy without imitating anything, so may music. In both cases the description ‘gloomy’ ascribes a dispositional property, that is, it refers to the capacity the landscape and piece of music have of making us gloomy ( Of the Nature of that Imitation , part II, 23). Once more, expression and imitation go separate ways.

Although perhaps less radically than their French or English counterparts, German intellectuals also increasingly questioned the role of imitation in music.

The philosopher and scientist Johann Georg Sulzer (1720–1779) still adheres to a rather orthodox view of imitation in music, holding that music imitates impassioned speech (Sulzer 1774, “Melody” [1792: III, 370–371; 1995: 91–92]). He also extends this account to instrumental music, and holds that music that fails to express emotions is worthless (Sulzer 1774, “Instrumental music” [1792: II, 677–679; 1995: 95–97]).

Johann Mattheson (1681–1764), the chief Affektenlehre theorist, embraces a Cartesian, physiological explanation of musical expression as the arousal of emotion produced by music’s action on the animal spirits (this is the standard view of Mattheson’s theory—see Lippman 1992: 115–116; for an alternative interpretation, see Kivy 1984). Thus, the musician who wishes to compose music expressive of an emotion will have to conform to the movements of the animal spirits associated with that emotion. This view alters the connection between emotional expression and imitation, as expression is no longer dependent on the imitation of impassioned speech.

Johann Gottfried von Herder (1744–1803) retains the idea that music is an imitative art, whose subjects are

all such things and incidents as are most eminently characterized by motion and sound; these include all species of motions, sounds, voices, passions expressed through sounds, and so on. (Herder 1769: I, 19)

This follows from the nature of music: whereas painting is the art of spatial coexistence, music is that of succession. It is by respecting these natural boundaries that the arts may achieve their effects. Thus,

music, which works wholly through the succession of time, must never make the depiction of objects in space its main object, as inexperienced bunglers do. (Herder 1769: I, 16)

There are similarities between Herder’s philosophy of music and Rousseau’s. Herder also proposes that today’s music and language may have a common ancestor, the main function of which was expressive (Herder 1772: part I, section III, 1; Herder 1769: IV, 8).

Herder is skeptical with regard to the role of mathematical or physical explanations in musical aesthetics, as these fail to explain our first-person hedonic and emotional responses. Much like Rousseau, he finds fault in Rameau on these grounds (Herder 1769: IV, 6). However, Herder does not abandon scientific explanations altogether, and in fact appeals to physiology to advance his own hypothesis (Herder 1769: IV, 6). While the details of this proposed explanation might be uninteresting, it is noteworthy that, by appealing to a causal explanation, Herder is weakening the link between expression and imitation.

Music was a lifelong concern for Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), whose musical writings touch on an impressive variety of topics, from music notation and theory to core philosophical concerns such as musical value and expressiveness. Rousseau was also the author of a remarkably successful opera, Le Devin du Village (1752), performed around four hundred times over the course of the fifty years following its premiere.

A contributor to Diderot and D’Alembert’s Encyclopédie (1751), Rousseau embarked on a systematic rejection of the views defended by Jean-Philippe Rameau (1683–1764), the leading music theorist at the time. Rousseau’s rejection of Rameau was not simply a rejection of his music theory, but rather of the entire musical practice it was supposed to justify, that is, French music of the time.

Rousseau’s Letter on French Music (1753) may be seen as an episode in the so-called querelle des bouffons , a dispute concerning the relative merits of Italian and French opera that was prompted by the 1752 Paris performance of Giovanni Battista Pergolesi’s La serva padrona . In the Letter , Rousseau takes the side of Italian music, holding that its superiority over French music is ultimately due to the Italian language, which is more melodious and better articulated than French. French music attempts to address the shortcoming of its language by adopting complex harmonic structures, but Rousseau believes that this only further hinders its expressive potential. He observes how Italian music is more moving not in spite of its use of chords that are not completely filled out, but precisely because of this feature. In the Letter , Rousseau also develops the principle of “unity of melody” ( unité de mélodie ), according to which music ought to present the listener with one single salient melody at any time, the other voices playing a subsidiary and supportive role. It is from this melodic unity that music derives its capacity to move the listener, and in this resides music’s value. The concept of unity of melody is further elaborated in a dedicated entry of Rousseau’s Dictionary of Music (1768), where he also states that his Devin du Village was an attempt to put that principle into practice (Rousseau 1768, “Unity of Melody”; on unity of melody, see Riley 2004: chapter 2, and Waeber 2009).

Rousseau’s polemical view of harmony as a hindrance to melodic development, as well as the consequent condemnation of French music, found a natural target in Rameau, who defended himself on various occasions (Rameau’s responses are collected in Scott 1998; on the debate, see Verba 2016: chapters 2 and 3). In his Traité de l’harmonie (1722), Rameau had already stated that melody is merely a part of harmony, and in his subsequent Nouveau système de musique théorique , he had attempted to ground the tonal system in the phenomenon of upper partial harmonics, the faint overtones that are produced whenever any note is struck. This means that there is strictly speaking no pure melody, as no note is ever heard in isolation from the harmonics it generates. The ascending series of upper harmonics, Rameau argues, contains the key to tonal harmony. In his Encyclopédie article “Dissonance”, Rousseau accepts that harmony may be partly grounded in the structure of the harmonic series, but presses Rameau on the origin of the minor third, an interval that is as crucial to tonal harmony as it is absent from the series. More important than these technical qualms is Rousseau’s fundamental methodological difference from Rameau. While Rameau’s musical aesthetics depends on a theory of music including mathematical and physical constructs inaccessible from the mere experience of listening, Rousseau considers such experience the ultimate judge of musical value, and holds that it points to melody as the part of music that is responsible for its emotional impact on the listener (see O’Dea 1995: 19–20). Insofar as it concerns the appropriate level of explanation of musical phenomena, the contrast between Rousseau and Rameau is not unlike the one between Aristoxenian and Pythagorean approaches to harmonics (see §1.2 ).

Rousseau’s views on the expressive power of music are further elaborated in his Essay on the Origin of Languages (1781), in which he argues that music and natural languages developed out of a common source, a language used for the expression of feelings (Rousseau 1781: chapter XII, “Origin of music”; see Thomas 1995: chapter 5). Following this common origin, both language and music underwent a process of decay. Languages developed in order to communicate increasingly complex thoughts, but lost expressive power, especially after the emergence of writing (Rousseau 1781: chapters V–VI). Thus, Plato’s Greece, Rousseau states, had no shortage of philosophers, but lacked musicians (Rousseau 1781: chapter XIX). Regarding this remark, Martinelli (2012 [2019: 62]) observes:

Anticipating the line of reasoning that would later be adopted by Nietzsche, Rousseau openly contrasted music and philosophy, strongly undermining the tradition that saw them as sisters.

According to Rousseau, music degenerated along with language and gradually lost its original expressive power. This happened as free melodic phrases progressively turned into regimented musical systems, in which harmony and counterpoint were introduced in order to compensate for the loss of natural melody (Rousseau 1781: chapter XIX).

It is tempting, though perhaps imprecise, to see in Rousseau’s view a precursor of the musilanguage hypothesis, recently proposed by Steven Brown (1999; on this, see Waeber 2013; Mithen 2005 advances a view similar to Brown’s).

As is apparent from his hypothesis concerning the origins of music, Rousseau thinks that the expression of emotions is music’s main function. A qualified notion of imitation plays a crucial role in this. While Rousseau accepts the eighteenth century view of art as imitation (Rousseau 1768, “Imitation”), he is also clear in stating that musical imitation is different from the kinds we find in other art forms. Music does not imitate the human passions or other objects by presenting us with their sonic equivalent, but rather by arousing in the listener the emotions that the object would give rise to. In Rousseau’s words,

It will not represent these things directly, but will arouse the same movements in the soul that are experienced in seeing them. (Rousseau 1768, “Imitation”)

It is because of this that musical imitation is not confined to one sense modality. If painting may represent only objects of sight,

[m]usic would seem to have the same limits with respect to hearing; nevertheless, it portrays everything, even objects which are only visible: by an almost inconceivable magic trick it seems to put the eye in the ear, and the greatest marvel of an Art that acts only by motion is to be able to form even the image of rest. Night, sleep, solitude, and silence are counted among Music’s great portraits. (Rousseau 1768, “Imitation”; similar claims on musical imitation are made elsewhere in Rousseau’s oeuvre, see Rousseau 1768, “Opera”, and Rousseau 1781: chapter XVI)

Effectively, the imitation that Rousseau considers central to music is the arousal of an emotion that is specific enough to be associated with a given object. Thus, while Rousseau is not skeptical with regard to music’s capacity to imitate worldly objects, he is able to defend this view because he redefines imitation in terms of emotional arousal. In this sense, he is still representative of a progressive shift away from a view of music as imitation.

Despite its charm, Rousseau’s view of musical imitation does not seem to withstand critical scrutiny. It is unconvincing as an explanation of the musical imitation of emotions. It may be though that an emotion we perceive always corresponds to another emotion we feel, and thus that we could depict the former by arousing the latter. But in fact, we may respond to, e.g., rage with a variety of emotions, from more rage, to fear, disappointment, schadenfreude, etc. The theory is only more implausible when it comes to the depiction of objects other than emotions, as the same object may arouse very different emotions, depending on the subject’s disposition and beliefs about it.

While his comments on music are at times disparaged as lacking artistic sensitivity, Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) is arguably the first major modern philosopher to discuss instrumental music in the context of a systematic account of the arts. His influence on subsequent musical thinking, and particularly on the formalist strand, is undeniable (see the entry on history of western philosophy of music: since 1800, section 1.6 ), but more controversial is whether he himself defends a variety of formalism. Kant’s main discussion of music is contained in the first section of the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790), but some remarks are also found in his Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (1798).

Kant’s views on music follow from an account of beauty that must be briefly reconstructed. Kant contrasts the beautiful , which aspires to universality, with the agreeable , which is subjective and idiosyncratic. According to Kant, when we ascribe beauty to objects we are making judgments of taste. These are subjective judgments, and include a feeling of pleasure. In this sense, judgments of taste are quite like judgments of agreeableness. The beautiful, however, is different from the agreeable in that it requires disinterested pleasure ( interessenloses Wohlgefallen ), that is, pleasure that does not presuppose the existence of its object. For example, I may find beautiful an imagined tune or painting, but I can’t find a refreshing drink agreeable if I merely think about it (Kant 1790: §2).

As they do not depend on concepts, and essentially include a subjective element of pleasure, judgments of taste are non-cognitive, and cannot therefore aspire to the same general validity as, say, mathematical proofs. However, judgments of taste are universal. When one judges an object to be beautiful, one is also at the same time asserting that anyone ought to find it beautiful (Kant 1790: §6–7). This again stands in contrast with the agreeable. When I judge the taste of calvados to be pleasant, I am not requiring general assent; in contrast, the pleasure associated with a work of music is one I expect anyone to feel—it is a beautiful piece of music.

The non-conceptual universality of judgments of taste is grounded in what Kant calls “the free play of the imagination and the understanding” (Kant 1790: §9). Ordinary perceptual and cognitive activities require the cooperation of imagination and understanding (here it is important to keep in mind that Kant considers imagination to be involved in perception) but in these cases imagination is guided by concepts. In the free play required by judgments of taste, imagination and understanding interact unconstrained by concepts, but in a way that is common to all human beings (Kant 1790: §20 ff.).

Kant distinguishes between agreeable and beautiful arts. While both involve pleasure, agreeable arts merely aim at arousing enjoyment, whereas beautiful arts involve cognition (Kant 1790: §44). The apparent ambiguity in Kant’s remarks on music runs so deep that he may seem to contradict himself even on the status of music as a beautiful art. He lists Tafelmusik (light music composed to be a background accompaniment to dining) alongside the art of telling amusing stories and jokes as an example of agreeable art, and adds that this kind of music is supposed to encourage conversation “without anyone paying the least attention to its composition” (Kant 1790: §44). In the “Remark” that concludes the first section of the Critique , Kant once more lists music alongside the joke as an agreeable art. However, elsewhere in the same work Kant clearly counts music a beautiful art, ranking it alongside poetry and painting (§44, 191). More importantly, Kant discusses music in §51, where he introduces his division of the beautiful arts. Samantha Matherne (2014: 135–138) has argued that Kant’s apparent hesitation is actually grounded in a different attitude we may take to music. If we attend to the bodily effect of the piece, music will be merely agreeable, whereas a focus on the formal structure of the work will make possible a judgment of taste, and thus music may be found beautiful.

A final point on musical beauty is worthy of mention. Kant distinguishes between free and adherent ( anhängend ) beauty. Adherent beauty presupposes a concept of the object’s purpose. Thus, a work of architecture is judged beautiful or not according to its success or otherwise in housing people, institutions, or businesses. The resulting judgment of taste is characterized by Kant as impure. Free beauty does not presuppose any concept. As examples of free beauty, Kant mentions abstract patterns, and instrumental music, “indeed all music without a text” (Kant 1790: §16). In general, when Kant discusses music he has pure instrumental music in mind. If one considers that previous thinkers devoted almost exclusive attention to vocal music, this is a significant shift in focus, and one that will be confirmed by the philosophy of music following Kant.

A further ambiguity is represented by Kant’s apparent commitment both to a variety of musical formalism, according to which musical beauty uniquely resides in the relationship between its component parts, and to the idea that music is expressive of emotions. This is a manifestation of a general tension in Kant’s aesthetics (see Guyer 1977). A formalist tendency is evident when Kant claims that the proper object of the pure judgment of taste in music is composition, by which he means the arrangement of tones (Kant 1790: §14). Later on, Kant states that music “merely plays with sensations” (Kant 1790: §53), offering this in support of his claims regarding music’s low rank among the arts.

Despite these apparent professions of formalism, Kant also stresses music’s connection to the sphere of emotions. Particularly, he seems to accept a version of the Affektenlehre , according to which works of music may arouse specific emotions in the listener. In §53, Kant affirms that music may convey an emotion because of its analogy with the tone of voice typical of impassioned speech (see also Kant 1798: §18).

In the face of these textual ambiguities, an option is to adopt a formalist interpretation and hold that Kant was merely paying lip service to the Affektenlehre (Kivy 2009: 50 ff.; Schueller 1955: 224–25). However, other scholars deny that Kant was a formalist. Young (2020) attributes to him an imitation theory of expressiveness: music imitates the tones characteristic of impassioned speech. Matherne (2014) attempts to reconcile formalist and expressivist elements in Kant’s thought. Crucial to her interpretation is the concept of an aesthetic idea, which Kant defines as

that representation of the imagination that occasions much thinking though without it being possible for any determinate thought, i.e., concept, to be adequate to it. (Kant 1790: §49)

Aesthetic ideas are imaginative representations that cannot be exhausted by any given concept—think of an abstract painting and of the multitude of things it could look like or symbolize. Aesthetic ideas are crucially involved in our experience of the beautiful, and Kant goes as far as to define beauty as the expression of aesthetic ideas (Kant 1790: §51). In his discussion of music, Kant states that the form of a composition—he explicitly mentions “harmony and melody”—expresses

the aesthetic ideas of a coherent whole of an unutterable fullness of thought, corresponding to a certain theme, which constitutes the dominant affect in the piece. (Kant 1790: §53)

Here the expression of a piece’s overarching emotional character, a central concern for the Affektenlehre , is explicitly linked to the piece’s formal structure. Matherne (2014: 134) concludes that Kant is defending what she terms “expressive formalism”, a view according to which music is able to express aesthetic ideas pertaining to the realm of emotions, and does so by means of its formal structure.

Kant’s view of music’s relative value as an art has also been an object of critical attention (Weatherston 1996; Parret 1998). Kant ranks the arts according to two distinct criteria. When it comes to “charm and movement of the mind” (Kant 1790: §53), music is first among all of the arts, as it arouses emotions more deeply than any other art form. It is clear that Kant does not consider this criterion particularly important to artistic value. Additionally, music occupies the bottom of the hierarchy when one ranks the arts according to the second criterion, that is, “in terms of the culture that they provide for the mind” (Kant 1790: §53). To provide culture for the mind is described by Kant as to contribute to the enlargement of the faculties of imagination and understanding—think again of an abstract painting, and how it may enrich our capacity to give visible form to some ideas.

While they may raise various difficult interpretive issues, Kant’s views on music have more than a purely historical interest. Some contemporary commentators and philosophers of music have suggested that they might be brought to bear on current debates (see Bicknell 2002; Ginsborg 2011: 337; Matherne 2014: 139–140).

Regardless of whether Kant’s formalism is or not a nineteenth century construction, his awareness of music’s purely formal aspect signals a change in Western philosophy of music. Vocal music is no longer the center of theoretical speculation. The philosophical problems that music poses are first and foremost those posed by pure instrumental music, and it is its nature that must be clarified if one is to understand music’s relation to language, concepts, and emotions.

  • Adamson, Peter, 2007, Al-KindĪ , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195181425.001.0001
  • Albert the Great, Liber de Causis Proprietatum Elementorum , translated in Albert the Great: On the Causes of the Properties of the Elements , Irven M. Resnick (trans.), Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.
  • Aristides Quintilianus, De Musica , translated in Barker 1990: 399–535. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511585753.013
  • Aristotle, Metaphysics , in Barnes 2014.
  • –––, On the Heavens , in Barnes 2014.
  • –––, On the Soul , in Barnes 2014.
  • –––, Poetics , in Barnes 2014.
  • –––, Politics , in Barnes 2014.
  • Aristoxenus, Elementa Harmonica , translated in Barker 1990: 126–184. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511585753.008
  • Artusi, Giovanni Maria, 1600, L’Artusi, overo Delle imperfettioni della moderna musica (L’Artusi or Of the Imperfections of Modern Music), Venetia: Vincenti.
  • Augustine, “The Pleasures Taken in Hearing”, in Confessions , ch. XXXIII; translated in Strunk 1950: 73–75.
  • –––, De Musica , translated by Robert Catesby Taliaferro in Augustine’s The Immortality of the Soul, the Magnitude of the Soul, On Music, the Advantage of Believing, On Faith in Things Unseen (Fathers of the Church 4), Ludwig Schopp (ed.), Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 2002.
  • Avison, Charles, 1775, An Essay on Musical Expression , third edition, London: Printed for Lockyer Davis. First edition 1752
  • Barker, Andrew (ed.), 1990, Greek Musical Writings, Volume 2: Harmonic and Acoustic Theory , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511585753
  • –––, 2007, The Science of Harmonics in Classical Greece , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511482465
  • –––, 2014, “Pythagorean Harmonics”, in A History of Pythagoreanism , Carl A. Huffman (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 185–203. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139028172.010
  • Barnes, Jonathan (ed.), 2014, The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation , one-volume digital edition, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Batteux, Charles, 1746, Les Beaux Arts réduits á un même principe , Paris: Durand; translated as The Fine Arts Reduced to a Single Principle , J. O. Young (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015. doi:10.1093/actrade/9780198747116.book.1
  • Beattie, James, 1779, “Essay on Poetry and Music, as they affect the Mind”, in his Essays , third edition, London: Printed for E. and C. Dilly, 3–291. [ Beattie 1779 available online ]
  • Bicknell, Jeanette, 2002, “Can Music Convey Semantic Content? A Kantian Approach”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 60(3): 253–261. doi:10.1111/1540-6245.00072
  • Boethius, De Institutione Musica , extracts translated in Strunk 1950: 79–86.
  • Bowman, Wayne D., 1998, Philosophical Perspectives on Music , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Boyé, 1779, L’Expression musicale, mise au rang des chimères (Musical Expression Placed Among the Chimeras), Paris: Esprit.
  • Brancacci, Aldo, 2007, “Democritus’ Mousika”, in Democritus: Science, The Arts, and the Care of the Soul , Aldo Brancacci and Pierre-Marie Morel (eds.), Leiden: Brill, 181–205. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004151604.i-352.41
  • Brown, Steven, 1999, “The ‘Musilanguage’ Model of Music Evolution”, in The Origins of Music , Steven Brown, Björn Merker, and Christina Wallin (eds.), Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 271–300. doi:10.7551/mitpress/5190.003.0022
  • Budd, Malcolm, 1985, Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories , London/Boston: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203420218
  • Caccini, Giulio, 1600 [1950], Dedication to “Euridice” , translated in Strunk 1950: 370–372.
  • Capella, Martianus, De nuptiis Philologiae et Mercurii ; translated as “The Marriage of Philology and Mercury”, in Martianus Capella and the Seven Liberal Arts. Volume II: The Marriage of Philology and Mercury , William H. Stahl, Richard Johnson, and E. L. Burge (trans.), New York: Columbia University Press, 1977.
  • Cassiodorus, “Of Music”, in Institutiones , bk 2, ch. 5, translated in Strunk 1950: 87–92.
  • Chabanon, Michel-Paul Guy de, 1779, Observations sur la musique, et principalement sur la métaphysique de l’art , Paris; translated as Observations on Music and Principally on the Metaphysics of Art , in Fubini 1994: 378–383.
  • D’Alembert, Jean Le Rond, 1759, “De la liberté de la musique”, in Mêlanges de littérature, d’histoire, et de philosophie , new edition, Amsterdam, volume 4: 383–462. Extracts translated as “On the Freedom of Music” in Fubini 1994: 85–91.
  • Descartes, René, 1649, Les Passions de l’âme , Paris: Henry Le Gras; translated as The Passions of the Soul , Stephen Voss (trans.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1989.
  • –––, 1650, Compendium musicae , Utrecht, translated as Compendium of Music , Walter Robert (trans.), Rome: American Institute of Musicology, 1961.
  • Diderot, Didier, 1760, Le Neveu de Rameau ou La Satire seconde , Paris. Extracts translated as Rameau’s Nephew , in Fubini 1994: 104–111.
  • Du Bos, Jean-Baptiste, 1719, Réflexions critiques sur la poésie et sur la peinture (Critical Reflections on Poetry and Painting), Paris: Jean Mariette.
  • Dyer, Joseph, 2007, “The Place of Musica in Medieval Classifications of Knowledge”, Journal of Musicology , 24(1): 3–71. doi:10.1525/jm.2007.24.1.3
  • Eriugena, John Scottus, Periphyseon , translated in Periphyseon (The Division of Nature) , Inglis Patric Sheldon-Williams (trans.), translation revised by John Joseph O’Meara, Montréal: Bellarmin, 1987.
  • Euclid (attr.), Sectio Canonis , translated in Barker 1990: 190–208. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511585753.009
  • Fellerer, Karl Gustav, 1953, “Church Music and the Council of Trent”, The Musical Quarterly , 39(4): 576–594. doi:10.1093/mq/XXXIX.4.576
  • Fubini, Enrico, 1976, Estetica musicale dall’antichità al Settecento , Torino: G. Einaudi; translated in Fubini 1991.
  • –––, 1987, Estetica musicale dal Settecento a oggi , expanded edition, Torino: G. Einaudi; translated in Fubini 1991. First edition in 1964.
  • –––, 1991, The History of Music Aesthetics , Michael Hatwell (trans.), Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Macmillan. Includes Fubini 1976 and 1987 in translation.
  • –––, 1994, Music and Culture in Eighteenth-Century Europe: A Source Book , translated from the original sources by Wolfgang Freis, Lisa Gasbarrone, and Michael Louis Leone, translation edited by Bonnie J. Blackburn, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Original Italian edition, Musica e cultura nel Settecento europeo , Torino: EDT, 1987.
  • Galilei, Vincenzo, 1581 [1950], Dialogo della musica antica e della moderna ( Dialogue of Ancient and Modern Music ), extracts translated in Strunk 1950: 302–322.
  • Ginsborg, Hannah, 2011, “Kant”, in The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music , Theodore Gracyk and Andrew Kania (eds.), London: Routledge, 348–58.
  • Glarean, Heinrich, 1547, Dodecachordon (in Latin), Basel; translated by Clement A. Miller, American Institute of Musicology, 1965.
  • Guyer, Paul D., 1977, “Formalism and the Theory of Expression in Kant’s Aesthetics”, Kant-Studien , 68(1–4): 46–70. doi:10.1515/kant.1977.68.1-4.46
  • Halliwell, Stephen, 2002, The Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Hamilton, Andy, 2007, Aesthetics and Music , London: Continuum.
  • Herder, Johann Gottfried, 1769, Kritische Wälder. Oder Betrachtungen, die Wissenschaft und Kunst des Schönen betreffend , three volumes, Riga: Hartknoch. Two extracts translated as “Critical Forests” in Johann Gottfried Herder: Selected Writings on Aesthetics , Gregory Moore (trans./ed.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006, 51–290
  • –––, 1772 [2002], Abhandlung über den Ursprung der Sprache ; translated as “Treatise on the Origin of Language”, in Herder: Philosophical Writings , M. N. Forster (ed./trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002, 65–164. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139164634.007.
  • Huffman, Carl A. (ed./trans.), 1993, Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic: A Commentary on the Fragments and Testimonia with Interpretive Essays , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511597367
  • –––, 2005, Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, Philosopher, and Mathematician King , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511482533
  • Hutcheson, Francis, 1725, An Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design , part of An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises , London. Modern editon in Francis Hutcheson: An Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design , Peter Kivy (ed.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.
  • Isidore of Seville, Etymologiarum , extracts translated in Strunk 1950: 93–100.
  • Jorgensen, Larry M., 2012, “Descartes on Music: Between the Ancients and the Aestheticians”, The British Journal of Aesthetics , 52(4): 407–424. doi:10.1093/aesthj/ays041
  • Kant, Immanuel, 1790 [2000], Kritik der Urteilskraft , Berlin/Libau: Lagarde und Friedrich; translated as Critique of the Power of Judgment , Paul Guyer (trans./ed.), Eric Matthews (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511804656
  • –––, 1798, Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht , Königsberg : Bey Friedrich Nicolovius; translated as Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View , Robert B. Louden (trans.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
  • Katz, Ruth and Carl Dahlhaus (eds.), 1993, Contemplating Music: Source Readings in the Aesthetics of Music , in four volumes, Stuyvesant: Pendragon Press.
  • Kivy, Peter, 1984, “Mattheson as Philosopher of Art”, The Musical Quarterly , 70(2): 248–265. doi:10.1093/mq/LXX.2.248
  • –––, 2009, Antithetical Arts: On the Ancient Quarrel Between Literature and Music , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199562800.001.0001
  • Le Huray, Peter and James Day, 1981, Music and Aesthetics in the Eighteenth and Early-Nineteenth Centuries , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, On Wisdom , translated in Leibniz 1989: 425–428.
  • –––, 1714, The Principles of Nature and of Grace, based on Reason , translated in Leibniz 1989: 636–642. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1426-7_67
  • –––, 1989, Philosophical Papers and Letters , Leroy E. Loemker (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1426-7
  • Levinson, Jerrold, 1997, Music in the Moment , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Lippman, Edward A., 1964, Musical Thought in Ancient Greece , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 1990, Musical Aesthetics: A Historical Reader , in three volumes, New York: Pendragon Press.
  • –––, 1992, A History of Western Musical Aesthetics , Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.
  • Martinelli, Riccardo, 2012 [2019], I Filosofi e la musica , Bologna: I mulino; translated as Philosophy of Music: A History , Sarah De Sanctis (trans.), Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter. doi:10.1515/9783110627411
  • Matherne, Samantha, 2014, “Kant’s Expressive Theory of Music”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 72(2): 129–145. doi:10.1111/jaac.12076
  • Mathiesen, Thomas, 1999, Apollo’s Lyre: Greek Music and Music Theory in Antiquity and the Middle Ages , Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.
  • Mattheson, Johann, 1739, Der Vollkommene Capellmeister ( The Perfect Chapelmaster ), Hamburg; translated in Johann Mattheson’s “Der Vollkommene Capellmeister”: A Revised Translation with Critical Commentary , Ernest C. Harriss (trans.), Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Research Press, 1981.
  • Mersenne, Marin, 1636, Harmonie universelle , Paris: Sébastien Cramoisy.
  • Mews, Constant J., 2011, “Questioning the Music of the Spheres in Thirteenth-Century Paris: Johannes de Grocheio and Jerome de Moravia OP”, in Knowledge, Discipline and Power in the Middle Ages , Joseph Canning, Edmund J. King, and Martial Staub (eds), Leiden: Brill, pp. 111–112.
  • Mithen, Steven, 2005, The Singing Neanderthal: The Origins of Music, Language, Mind and Body , London: Orion.
  • Monteverdi, Giulio Cesare, 1607 [1950], “Declaration”, in Il quinto libro de’ madrigali , translated in Strunk 1950: 405–412.
  • Morellet, André, 1771, De l’expression en musique, et de l’imitation dans les arts , Mercure de France , November 1771, 113–143; reprinted in his Mélanges de littérature et de philosophie du 18e siècle , Paris: veuve Lepetit, 1818, volume 4, pp. 366–404.
  • Murray, Penelope and Peter Wilson, 2004, “Introduction: Mousikē, not Music”, in Music and the Muses: The Culture of Mousikē in the Classical Athenian City , Penelope Murray and Peter Wilson (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–8.
  • O’Dea, Michael, 1995, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Music, Illusion, and Desire , New York: St. Martin’s Press.
  • Palisca, Claude V., 1989, The Florentine Camerata: Documentary Studies and Translations , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • –––, 2006, Music and Ideas in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries , Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
  • Parret, Herman, 1998, “Kant on Music and the Hierarchy of the Arts”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 56(3): 251–264. doi:10.2307/432365
  • Philodemus, De Musica , in Katz and Dahlhaus 1993, vol. I, pp. 286–287.
  • Plato, Laches , in Plato 1997: 664–686.
  • –––, Laws , in Plato 1997: 1318–1616.
  • –––, Phaedo , in Plato 1997: 49–100.
  • –––, Republic , in Plato 1997: 971–1223.
  • –––, Timaeus , in Plato 1997: 1224–1291.
  • –––, 1997, Plato: Complete Works , John M. Cooper (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
  • Ptolemy, Harmonics , translated in Barker 1990: 275–391. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511585753.012
  • Rameau, Jean-Philippe, 1722, Traité de l’harmonie réduite à ses principes naturels , Paris: Ballard.
  • –––, 1726, Nouveau système de musique théorique , Paris: Ballard.
  • Reid, Thomas, 1774, Lectures on the Fine Arts . Printed in Thomas Reid’s Lectures on the Fine Arts , Peter Kivy (ed.), The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.
  • Riley, Matthew, 2004, Musical Listening in the German Enlightenment: Attention, Wonder and Astonishment , London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315090702
  • Rocconi, Eleonora, 2012, “Aristoxenos and Musical Ethos”, in Aristoxenus of Tarentum: Discussion , Carl A. Huffman (ed.), New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 65–90.
  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1753, Lettre sur la musique française ; translated as Letter on French Music , in Scott 1998: 141–174.
  • –––, 1768, Dictionnaire de musique , Paris; translated as Dictionary of Music , in Scott 1998: 366–485.
  • –––, 1781, Essai sur l’origine des langues , Genève; translated as Essay on the Origin of Languages , in Scott 1998: 289–332.
  • Schofield, Malcolm, 2010, “Music All Pow’rful”, in Plato’s “Republic” , Mark L. McPherran (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 229–248. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511763090.013
  • Schueller, Herbert M., 1948, “‘Imitation’ and ‘Expression’ in British Music Criticism in the 18th Century”, The Musical Quarterly , 34(4): 544–566. doi:10.1093/mq/XXXIV.4.544
  • –––, 1955, “Immanuel Kant and the Aesthetics of Music”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 14(2): 218–247. doi:10.2307/425860
  • –––, 1988, The Idea of Music: An Introduction to Musical Aesthetics in Antiquity and the Middle Ages , Kalamazoo, MI: Medieval Institute Publications, Western Michigan University.
  • Scott, John T. (ed.), 1998, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Essay on the Origin of Language and Writings related to Music , Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.
  • Sextus Empiricus, Pros mousikous , translated as Against the Musicians , Denise Davidson Greaves (trans.), Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press, 1986.
  • Shehadi, Fadlou, 1995, Philosophies of Music in Medieval Islam , Leiden: Brill. doi:10.1163/9789004247215
  • Smith, Adam, “Of the Nature of that Imitation that Takes Place in what are called The Imitative Arts”, in Essays on Philosophical Subjects , Dublin, 1795; reprinted in Essays on Philosophical Subjects , W. P. D. Wightman and J. C. Bryce (eds.), Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1982.
  • Sörbom, Göran, 1994, “Aristotle on Music as Representation”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 52(1): 37–46. doi:10.2307/431583
  • Strunk, Oliver, 1950, Source Readings in Music History: From Classical Antiquity through the Romantic Era , New York: Norton & Company.
  • Sulzer, Johann Georg, 1771/1774 [1792, 1995], Allgemeine Theorie der schönen Künste , two volumes; second edition in four volumes, Johann Gottfried Dyck and Georg Schaz (eds.), Leipzig, 1792. Extracts from the second edition translated by Thomas Christensen as “General Theory of the Fine Arts”, in Aesthetics and the Art of Composition in the German Enlightenment: Selected Writings of Johann Georg Sulzer and Heinrich Christoph Koch , Nancy Kovaleff Baker and Thomas Christensen (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, 25–108.
  • Thomas, Downing A., 1995, Music and the Origins of Language: Theories from the French Enlightenment , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511582608
  • Tinctoris, Johannes, 1477, “Liber de arte contrapuncti”, translated as The art of counterpoint , Albert Seay (trans.), Rome: American Institute of Musicology, 1961.
  • –––, c. 1476, Proportionale Musices , translated in Strunk 1950: 193–196.
  • –––, Complexus effectuum musices , translated in On the Dignity and the Effects of Music: Two Fifteenth-century Treatises , Reinhard Strohm and J. Donald Cullington (eds.), London: Institute of Advanced Musical Studies, King’s College London, 1996.
  • Verba, Cynthia, 2016, Music and the French Enlightenment: Rameau and the Philosophes in Dialogue , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199381029.001.0001
  • Waeber, Jacqueline, 2009, “Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s ‘Unité de Mélodie’”, Journal of the American Musicological Society , 62(1): 79–143. doi:10.1525/jams.2009.62.1.79
  • –––, 2013, “A Corruption of Rousseau? The Quest for the Origins of Music and Language in Recent Scientific Discourses”, part of the Colloquy: “Rousseau in 2013: Afterthoughts on a Tercentenary”, Journal of the American Musicological Society , 66(1): 284–289. doi:10.1525/jams.2012.66.1.251
  • Weatherston, Martin, 1996, “Kant’s Assessment of Music in the ‘Critique of Judgment’”, The British Journal of Aesthetics , 36(1): 56–65. doi:10.1093/bjaesthetics/36.1.56
  • Webb, Daniel, 1769, Observations on the Correspondence between Poetry and Music , London: Printed for J. Dodsley.
  • Wilkinson, Lancelot P, 1938, “Philodemus on Ethos in Music”, The Classical Quarterly , 32(3–4): 174–181. doi:10.1017/S0009838800025878
  • Witkin, Robert W., 1998, Adorno on Music , London/New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315006048
  • Young, James O., 2020, “Kant’s Musical Antiformalism”, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 78(2): 171–182. doi:10.1111/jaac.12712
  • –––, forthcoming, History of Western Philosophy of Music , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Zarlino, Gioseffo, 1558 [1950], Istituzioni Armoniche , parts of bk III, chs 26, 27, 29, 30, 31, 40, 71; bk IV, chs 30, 32, 33 translated in Strunk 1950: 229–261.
  • –––, 1588, Sopplimenti Musicali , Venice: Francesco de’ Franceschi.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

aesthetics: British, in the 18th century | aesthetics: French, in the 18th century | aesthetics: German, in the 18th century | al-Farabi | Archytas | Aristotle, General Topics: aesthetics | Descartes, René | Du Bos, Jean-Baptiste | Herder, Johann Gottfried von | Kant, Immanuel: aesthetics and teleology | Mersenne, Marin | music, philosophy of | music: history of western philosophy of, since 1800 | Philodemus | Plato: aesthetics | Pythagoras | Pythagoreanism | Rousseau, Jean Jacques

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Stephen Davies, Andrew Kania, James O. Young, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on a draft of this entry.

Copyright © 2021 by Matteo Ravasio < matteo @ pku . edu . cn >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

  • T.H.E – Podcasts

T.H.E - Music Essentials

Writing An Essay On Music Thematic: 5 Key Elements

essay on music

Essays about music can be rather hard if you’d rather play music and express your emotions through it rather than share them and your opinions in written form. Those who struggle with such tasks usually address EssayWritingService.com to work on engaging projects and practice. But what if you have to write it by yourself?

Music is a massive subject, with myriad genres, instruments, theoretical, and cultural facets to examine in an essay. The complexity of the subject is intimidating to the uninitiated.

That’s why some writers crafting content on music may find a college essay writing service to be of use at some point in their writing process.

In this article, we’ll assess several key elements of an essay on a musical theme. The processes we’ll cover include analysis, technical work, comparative studies, and more.

We’ll also discuss some great music essay topics if you’re stuck for ideas; remember that a hypothesis is the most crucial element of any essay. Hopefully, the elements here will find a happy home in your music essay and help you get a top mark.

1) Writing about music that you love:

Whether it’s disco or desert-rock, EDM or classical, if you choose a genre or subject you love, the process of writing becomes much easier. All those internal references and resonances can come out in an essay and help demonstrate how much of an expert you are on your theme of choice.

essay on music thematic

2) Writing technically and analytically:

Essays cannot simply describe a song or a piece of music. While the phenomenological approach can be useful in certain essays, it shouldn’t make up the bulk of your essay. Writing analytically about music also does not have to mean talking chords, scales, and tunings. Analysis can be related to a corollary, like the means of publishing, the types of audience, the social scenes involved, and the impact on culture or music theory.

Music analysis is a much more technical skill. Remember that when you’re writing an essay, you only really need to fulfil the criteria set out in the mark scheme. For a music essay, this mark scheme will likely sound like this “[the student] evaluates music by systemically deconstructing the score, determining any manipulations, relationships, elements, and compositional devices being used, and communicating judgements on these in a detailed and substantiated manner”.

That’s not likely a verbatim extract from your personal mark scheme, but it is a close approximation of those for song analysis essays. Be sure to double-check and work from your own mark scheme.

The general gist however is clear: use your music knowledge, evaluate what you hear and present it in a way that is both detailed and backed up by sources and citations – remember to cite the piece itself, either by the bar or the time in the song.

3) Making comparisons:

In the previous section, we talked about the use of musical knowledge and how judgements must be made in a detailed way. One method of judgement is the comparison; you can take time in your essay writing process to determine whether an element of the composition is related in some way to an element in another piece. What interesting lines of flight can you draw?

essay on music thematic

4) Choosing a good topic:

Should you be writing a dissertation, you will have to choose your own subject and delineate it in a way that shows you have found some novelty in the field. If you are looking for examples of topics, you can always dive through Wikipedia, it’s a great place to find connections between subjects and ideas.

Another way of coming up with a thesis and topics is to study your music collection. Go with something that interests you, or go with something you dislike and try to explain why you think it is such a poor showing. When doing the latter, remember that critique itself is an art form that shouldn’t be watered down into blunt punches and crass language.

5) Be an active participant:

When we usually listen to music, we’re doing so in a passive sense. Our ears are open for the melodies and harmonies to fall into, but are we actually listening? We may very well be enjoying the music, but unfortunately, enjoyment won’t get top marks. In order to write an essay about music we need to deconstruct it, and in order to do that we must listen very actively and attentively.

A tried and tested method for doing this is to select one musical element, for example, pitch or timbre, and listen to the entire song focusing solely on that aspect. Then, as you can surely guess, do the same with other aspects. Write down notes on everything that you notice. Once you’ve noted through all the relevant elements , you’ll have a lot of notes to work with and a great familiarity with the piece.

In summary, writing a solid essay on music requires attentive listening, knowledge of musical elements, and the ability to put into words the sensations and feelings evoked when listening to the piece. These skills can only be cultivated through practice and patience – it takes a certain amount of time to listen to each piece of music. So, start early and listen well.

RELATED ARTICLES MORE FROM AUTHOR

rammstein stadium tour

Rammstein Stadium Tour: 1st Leg Germany VS 2nd Leg Germany

hardstyle sample packs

Hardstyle Sample Packs: The Essential Tool For Every DJ’s Toolkit

what makes a spotify superstar

What Makes A Spotify Superstar? Unveiling Patterns From A Deep Dive On The Top 1000 Artists

Leave a reply cancel reply.

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Recent Posts

reinier zonneveld ai live music project

Reinier Zonneveld Debuts His AI Live Music Project At Brand New R² Festival

north coast music festival 2024 lineup

North Coast Music Festival Unveils Phase 2 Lineup Additions For 2024 Event

jessica audiffred don't speak

Jessica Audiffred And GG Magree Unleash Electronic Rendition Of No Doubt’s “Don’t Speak”

ferry corsten where the mountains grow

WTF!…Ferry Corsten Surprised Rotterdam Centraal Station With A Pop-Up DJ Set!

billy xane arkham

FMU Records Introduces Rising Australian Techno Talent Billy Xane Debut Single ‘Arkham’

Mary Lyon: The Geneticist Who Discovered That Women Are (Cellular) Mosaics

What galileo’s satellites are hiding, openmind books, scientific anniversaries, the eternal sound: from the phonograph to holophony, featured author, latest book, what is the purpose of music.

“Without music, life would be a mistake,” wrote the philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche . Albert Einstein, who was an accomplished violinist, said that nothing gave him as much pleasure as music , and that this would have been his occupation had he not pursued science. Today neuroscientists, musicologists, psychologists and anthropologists continue to ponder why humans enjoy music so much. The discovery of 40,000-year-ago bone flutes in a cave in Germany, perhaps the oldest musical instruments on record, suggests that music has accompanied Homo sapiens since ancient times. But what is its function?

The question has puzzled experts for centuries and there is still no conclusive answer. In the 5th century BC, the school of Pythagoras suggested that music governed the harmony of the stars , whereas current scientific research—from an evolutionary and biological perspective—considers that music serves rather to govern the harmony between human beings.

One of the purposes for music is social cohesion says Jeremy Montagu, a musician and professor at Oxford University. In an essay published in the journal Frontiers in Sociology , Montagu argues that music is so primitive that it predates language. He maintains that a mother’s humming to soothe her baby is music and that this likely happened before humans could speak.

According to Montagu, the bond that music establishes between mother and child is also present in a group of workers or in the ancestral men who danced and sang before a hunt or a battle. “In causing such bonding, [music] created not only the family, but society itself ,” he writes. During the lockdowns due to the COVID-19 pandemic, nothing helped connect people and break the sense of isolation as much as music , sung or played from balconies or through online videos.

Communicates emotions

The hypothesis that music played an essential role in the formation and survival of groups and in conflict mitigation is one of the most widely accepted. Mark Tramo of the Institute for Music & Brain Science at Harvard University defines it as a factor of social cohesion. “Men needed to organise to hunt and defend themselves. It paved the way for us to communicate with each other and to share emotions,” he explains. The emotional factor is essential; Montagu defines music as “sound that conveys emotion”.

The ability to communicate emotion is precisely what made music persist after the development of language. A study by psychologists at the University of London and the Austrian Academy of Sciences showed, for example, that even when listening to a short excerpt of a piece of music, an individual is more likely to perceive sadness or happiness in the face of another person, even if the latter maintains a neutral facial expression.

BBVA-OpenMind-Oliveira-Yanes-Musica_2

In its task of forging bonds between people, music also reveals one’s personality, according to a study by social psychology experts at the universities of Cambridge and Texas. The participants were asked to judge each other’s personality based solely on their list of ten favourite songs . Psychologists noted that the participants correctly identified the personality traits of their study partners and concluded that musical taste is a reliable source of information about an individual. A study led by Adrian North of Edinburgh’s Heriot-Watt University surveyed more than 36,000 people in over 60 countries to link musical preferences with personality traits . The results were curious; for example, classical and heavy metal music fans differ in age, but overlap quite closely in personality traits. According to North, they share a “love of the grandiose”. “They’re quite delicate things,” says the researcher. “Lots of heavy metal fans will tell you that they also like Wagner, because it’s big, loud and brash.”

Promotes happiness and creativity

Given music’s emotional capacity, it makes sense that we listen to music that makes us feel good. A study conducted by the Chemnitz University of Technology (Germany), which surveyed more than 800 people on the reasons that motivate them to listen to music, found that the main reasons are related to the regulation of arousal and mood and to achieve self-awareness, even more than social cohesion or communication. Studies have shown that about two-thirds of the population experience what is known as frisson , a pleasurable chill when listening to music that gives us goose bumps; some researchers have even dubbed it a “skin orgasm” . Researchers at Eastern Washington University showed that people more prone to this effect exhibit a personality trait called openness to experience , and that cognitive factors such as imagination or intellectual curiosity weigh even more heavily in this experience than purely emotional ones.

BBVA-OpenMind-Oliveira-Yanes-Musica_3

At a deeper level, scientists are exploring the brain mechanisms of musical experience. Research published in Nature and led by Daniel Levitin , neuroscientist and author of the book This is Your Brain on Music: The Science of a Human Obsession , indicates that music acts on the brain in a similar way to drugs, sex or food. Songs activate the frontal lobe, produce dopamine and act on the cerebellum, which is able to synchronise itself to the rhythm of the music, leading to pleasure . Both playing and listening to music stimulate the production of oxytocin, popularly known as the love hormone. Music “is like a toy for the brain,” says Levitin.

And that “toy” also stimulates creativity. While many people welcome absolute silence during tasks that require concentration, at least one study has found that a moderate level of ambient sound is more conducive to creativity than a lower level of noise, especially in the most creative people. Explanations have been provided by a phenomenon called stochastic resonance , whereby not only humans but also certain animals improve some of their functions under sensory stimulation.

BBVA-OpenMind-Oliveira-Yanes-Musica_4

In children’s brains, musical activity increases cognitive and motor skills . A team of neurologists at Harvard University found that children who have three years or more of training with musical instruments have better motor coordination and auditory discrimination skills, learn vocabulary more easily and have better non-verbal reasoning skills, which implies better understanding and analysis of visual information, such as identifying relationships, similarities and differences between shapes and patterns. Continued musical practice throughout the later years of schooling is associated with better grades in mathematics, science and language.

Music is therapeutic

Of all the functions of music, perhaps the most mysterious is its possible therapeutic use. The British neurologist Oliver Sacks reported in his books cases of patients with Alzheimer’s or Parkinson’s disease whose symptoms improved when they listened to songs . Other research shows that stroke patients who listen to music of their own choice not only improve their mood, but also their visual attention and ability to do other tasks . Neurological music therapy is now an active field of research that is attracting increasing interest .

BBVA-OpenMind-Oliveira-Yanes-Musica_5

In his book Music, the Brain, and Ecstasy: How Music Captures Our Imagination , composer and pianist Robert Jourdain writes that music “relaxes brain flow” while “stimulating and coordinating brain activities”. For him, this “magic” happens to all people. “Music lifts us from our frozen mental habits and makes our minds move in ways ordinarily cannot,” he states. Or in more direct words, as reggae genius Bob Marley sang in Trenchtown Rock , “one good thing about music, when it hits you, you feel no pain.”

Joana Oliveira  and  Javier Yanes

Related publications.

  • "Music conveys stories and emotions and connects people", Tod Machover (MIT)
  • Eric Clarke: Neuroscience, Anthropology and Sociology to Understand Music
  • Frontiers and Knowledge in Music? A Few Notes
  • Is Music Streaming a Sustainable Business?

More about Humanities

Communications, more publications about ventana al conocimiento (knowledge window), comments on this publication.

Morbi facilisis elit non mi lacinia lacinia. Nunc eleifend aliquet ipsum, nec blandit augue tincidunt nec. Donec scelerisque feugiat lectus nec congue. Quisque tristique tortor vitae turpis euismod, vitae aliquam dolor pretium. Donec luctus posuere ex sit amet scelerisque. Etiam sed neque magna. Mauris non scelerisque lectus. Ut rutrum ex porta, tristique mi vitae, volutpat urna.

Sed in semper tellus, eu efficitur ante. Quisque felis orci, fermentum quis arcu nec, elementum malesuada magna. Nulla vitae finibus ipsum. Aenean vel sapien a magna faucibus tristique ac et ligula. Sed auctor orci metus, vitae egestas libero lacinia quis. Nulla lacus sapien, efficitur mollis nisi tempor, gravida tincidunt sapien. In massa dui, varius vitae iaculis a, dignissim non felis. Ut sagittis pulvinar nisi, at tincidunt metus venenatis a. Ut aliquam scelerisque interdum. Mauris iaculis purus in nulla consequat, sed fermentum sapien condimentum. Aliquam rutrum erat lectus, nec placerat nisl mollis id. Lorem ipsum dolor sit amet, consectetur adipiscing elit.

Nam nisl nisi, efficitur et sem in, molestie vulputate libero. Quisque quis mattis lorem. Nunc quis convallis diam, id tincidunt risus. Donec nisl odio, convallis vel porttitor sit amet, lobortis a ante. Cras dapibus porta nulla, at laoreet quam euismod vitae. Fusce sollicitudin massa magna, eu dignissim magna cursus id. Quisque vel nisl tempus, lobortis nisl a, ornare lacus. Donec ac interdum massa. Curabitur id diam luctus, mollis augue vel, interdum risus. Nam vitae tortor erat. Proin quis tincidunt lorem.

Fanny Hesse, the Mother of Bacterial Cultures

Do you want to stay up to date with our new publications.

Receive the OpenMind newsletter with all the latest contents published on our website

OpenMind Books

  • The Search for Alternatives to Fossil Fuels
  • View all books

About OpenMind

Connect with us.

  • Keep up to date with our newsletter

Think you can get into a top-10 school? Take our chance-me calculator... if you dare. 🔥

Last updated March 22, 2024

Every piece we write is researched and vetted by a former admissions officer. Read about our mission to pull back the admissions curtain.

Blog > Essay Advice , Personal Statement > How to Write a Great College Essay About Music (with examples)

How to Write a Great College Essay About Music (with examples)

Admissions officer reviewed by Ben Bousquet, M.Ed Former Vanderbilt University

Written by Alex McNeil, MA Admissions Consultant

Key Takeaway

Ask any admissions officer if they’ve read a college essay about music, and they’ll definitely say yes. Between music extracurriculars and academic interests in music, it’s is one of the most common college essay topics.

So does that mean that you shouldn’t write your college essay about music?

Not necessarily. But as with any common college essay topic, some approaches are better than others.

Let’s get into it.

Why you should (and shouldn’t) write your Common App essay about music

As we explained in our Stanford Items exercise , writing your college essay on a common topic isn’t off-limits. In fact, most college essays share common topics and themes. Trying to find a completely unique, never-been-done-before topic is almost impossible. And writing about a quirky topic in hopes of coming across as unique usually backfires.

In other words, it’s likely that you’ll write about the same topic as someone else.

The problem arises, however, when you write about a common topic in a cliche way . Cliches are always a danger in college essays, but in especially college essay topics that tend to surface again and again.

To avoid cliches, your college essay about music needs to be deeply personal, specific, and meaningful. You’ll want to let go of any over-generalizations or truisms and focus on the details of your own story.

Because you’ll need to write meaningfully and vulnerably, you should only write your college essay about music if you have something genuine and significant to say.

The Best Ways to Approach Your College Essay about Music

College essays about music aren’t off the table, but you should be thoughtful in how you write about them. The following two approaches will help you avoid cliches and find an authentic, meaningful story that fulfills all the requirements of a personal statement .

Writing about music as an academic interest

If you’re interested in studying music in college, then you can consider writing your college essay about music as an academic interest. A college essay about your academic interest in music can show fantastic intellectual fit with a school.

Let’s say you want to study music theory or composition. You might write about a topic you find compelling, a problem you’ve solved, or even a recounting of your journey becoming interested in the subject.

Or maybe you’re an aspiring performer planning on studying music performance. As an admissions officer, I read outstanding essays about students performing their favorite pieces, creating emotional music projects, and teaching lessons to young children.

No matter your topic, your goal with this approach is to show an intellectual spark, a curiosity and passion that will demonstrate to your admissions officers that you’ll be a great addition to the music community on their campuses.

Writing poignantly about a deeply meaningful extracurricular

The previous approach is great if you want to study music, but what if music is just an extracurricular passion of yours? Don’t worry—you can still write about it.

In that case, the best way is to focus on meaning. Remember: personal statements should be deeply-meaningful reflections on your personal strengths.

To start, reflect on your music extracurricular. Is it playing guitar in a band? Playing trombone in your school’s symphony? Learning piano from your grandma? How your love of poetry turned into a love of songwriting?

Next, think about what strengths you have to showcase. If you play guitar in a band, maybe you want to highlight your collaborative spirit. If you love poetry and songwriting, perhaps you focus on your creativity.

Writing about your love of music in a way that draws upon your strengths will make sure that your Common App essay avoids the following two approaches and gives admissions officers a reason to admit you.

Approaches to Avoid

While the following two approaches aren’t necessarily bad, they are the most cliche ways of approaching a college essay about music. You might want to consider avoiding them.

An inauthentic tale of triumph

Let me tell you a cliche story.

When I was in fourth grade, I decided to join the school orchestra. I found it exceedingly difficult at first. No matter how hard I tried, I never could seem to place my fingers correctly on the fingerboard. Every sound I made mimicked a screeching cat. But I decided not to give up. I practiced every day after school and on the weekends. By the time I was in ninth grade, I had made it into my high school’s top orchestra.

Is that a lovely story? Yes, absolutely. Is it hearty enough for a college essay? No. While it tells a good narrative of growth and progress, it remains on the surface of the writer’s life. It comes across as a convenient way to brag about your strengths instead of exploring them in a genuine way. In this example, the story also focuses on events that happened way too far in the past.

A song that changed your life

This approach is by far the most common cliche in college essays about music. We’ve all been there: a favorite song that transports you to a moment in your life whenever you hear it. It makes sense that you’d want to write about yours.

But there’s a problem with this approach. Too often, it reads as trite or unoriginal, and the end result usually doesn’t say much about the writer. And when it does, the message an admissions officer gets doesn’t typically give them any more reason to admit you. Since you want your college essay to be meaningful, even vulnerable, and strengths-based, you’re better off choosing another topic that better speaks to who you are.

Key Takeaways + Examples

College essays about music aren’t for everyone. But when you get it right, you can strike the perfect chord with admissions officers (you’re welcome for the pun).

As you go, dig deep, find something genuinely personal, and try to avoid the most common and cliche ways of approaching the topic.

Want to see some examples of college essays about music before you get started? Check out our examples, The Time Machine and The Band .

Liked that? Try this next.

post preview thumbnail

The Incredible Power of a Cohesive College Application

post preview thumbnail

How to Write a College Essay (Exercises + Examples)

post preview thumbnail

20 College Essay Examples (Graded by Former Admissions Officers)

post preview thumbnail

How A Selective Admissions Office Reads 50k Applications In A Season

"the only actually useful chance calculator i’ve seen—plus a crash course on the application review process.".

Irena Smith, Former Stanford Admissions Officer

We built the best admissions chancer in the world . How is it the best? It draws from our experience in top-10 admissions offices to show you how selective admissions actually works.

Essay on Music for Students and Children

500+ words essay on music.

Music is a vital part of different moments of human life. It spreads happiness and joy in a person’s life. Music is the soul of life and gives immense peace to us. In the words of William Shakespeare, “If music is the food of love, play on, Give me excess of it; that surfeiting, The appetite may sicken, and so die.” Thus, Music helps us in connecting with our souls or real self.

Essay on Music

What is Music?

Music is a pleasant sound which is a combination of melodies and harmony and which soothes you. Music may also refer to the art of composing such pleasant sounds with the help of the various musical instruments. A person who knows music is a Musician.

The music consists of Sargam, Ragas, Taals, etc. Music is not only what is composed of men but also which exists in nature. Have you ever heard the sound of a waterfall or a flowing river ? Could you hear music there? Thus, everything in harmony has music. Here, I would like to quote a line by Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart, one of the greatest musicians, “The music is not in the notes, but in the silence between.”

Importance of Music:

Music has great qualities of healing a person emotionally and mentally. Music is a form of meditation. While composing or listening music ones tends to forget all his worries, sorrows and pains. But, in order to appreciate good music, we need to cultivate our musical taste. It can be cited that in the Dwapar Yug, the Gopis would get mesmerized with the music that flowed from Lord Krishna’s flute. They would surrender themselves to Him. Also, the research has proved that the plants which hear the Music grow at a faster rate in comparison to the others.

Get the huge list of more than 500 Essay Topics and Ideas

Magical Powers of Music:

It has the power to cure diseases such as anxiety, depression, insomnia, etc. The power of Music can be testified by the legends about Tansen of his bringing the rains by singing Raag Megh Malhar and lighting lamps by Raga Deepak. It also helps in improving the concentration and is thus of great help to the students.

Conclusion:

Music is the essence of life. Everything that has rhythm has music. Our breathing also has a rhythm. Thus, we can say that there is music in every human being or a living creature. Music has the ability to convey all sorts of emotions to people. Music is also a very powerful means to connect with God. We can conclude that Music is the purest form of worship of God and to connect with our soul.

FAQs on Essay on Music:

Q.1. Why is Music known as the Universal Language?

Ans.1. Music is known as the Universal language because it knows no boundaries. It flows freely beyond the barriers of language, religion, country, etc. Anybody can enjoy music irrespective of his age.

Q.2. What are the various styles of Music in India?

Ans.2. India is a country of diversities. Thus, it has numerous styles of music. Some of them are Classical, Pop, Ghazals, Bhajans, Carnatic, Folk, Khyal, Thumri, Qawwali, Bhangra, Drupad, Dadra, Dhamar, Bandish, Baithak Gana, Sufi, Indo Jazz, Odissi, Tarana, Sugama Sangeet, Bhavageet, etc.

Customize your course in 30 seconds

Which class are you in.

tutor

  • Travelling Essay
  • Picnic Essay
  • Our Country Essay
  • My Parents Essay
  • Essay on Favourite Personality
  • Essay on Memorable Day of My Life
  • Essay on Knowledge is Power
  • Essay on Gurpurab
  • Essay on My Favourite Season
  • Essay on Types of Sports

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Download the App

Google Play

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Front Psychol

Editorial: The Evolution of Music

Aleksey nikolsky.

1 Braavo Enterprises, Los Angeles, CA, United States

Leonid Perlovsky

2 Department of Psychology, Northeastern University, Boston, MA, United States

Two decades ago, Wallin et al. ( 1999 ) opened a new page in the quest for the origins of music by integrating the methodologies and data coming from numerous disciplines:

  • physical anthropology
  • paleoneurobiology
  • biocultural evolution
  • systematic musicology
  • historical linguistics
  • developmental psychology

This volume updates this multi-disciplinary approach by further advancing the fields defined by Wallin et al. and by introducing and specifying new fields of inquiry:

  • musicological analysis
  • geomusicology
  • information theory
  • statistic modeling
  • (paleo)aesthetics
  • (paleo)phonology
  • biological motion

In addition, this volume addresses a number of interdisciplinary problems that were identified by the contributing authors 1 . The latter issue has recently become critical: the very idea of multidisciplinary study of music has been questioned. There is a growing conviction amongst Western scholars of ethnomusicological background that humanities and sciences are fundamentally split, and the scientific approach somehow introduces an “anti-humanitarian” bias (Parncutt, 2017 ). According to this view, specialists in sciences should adjust their methodologies to comply with the conventions of political correctness currently adopted by many Western specialists in musicology and social sciences. This view exploits the argument that the public trust in science supports the “scientific hegemony” in an ongoing cultural “warfare” between disciplines of art and science, thereby precluding the advance in human knowledge (Cohen, 2001 ). This argument was introduced half-a-century ago in a popular book by Snow ( 1964 ). Despite being convincingly debunked by Wilson ( 1998 ) and Gould ( 2003 ), it resurfaced again in the ideology of “new mysterianism,” propagated by Chomsky ( 2016 ) and McGinn ( 2015 ). Their intellectual weight has made the call for “humanizing” science more appealing to scientists.

Mysterianist and anti-scientific sentiments found fertile ground amongst many musicians and musicologists that regard a scientific approach as being “bound to the science lab” and therefore irrelevant to music practice—even detrimental to the expressive efficacy of music-makers (Woody, 2004 ). Indeed, differences in jargon between musicological 2 and psychoacoustic disciplines set a barrier against co-understanding, which preserves the popular myths about perception/production of music (Juslin et al., 2012 ). Many believe that music is incommensurable, irrational, and mystic—unsuitable for objective investigation (Dubal, 1985 ) and demanding an intuitive approach (Woody, 2000 ).

A big role in the spread of this attitude has been played by the ongoing trend of “scientism” in influential Western schools of composition, and the critical acclaim they have been receiving from well-established musical critics and musicologists (Regelski, 2014 ). Overwhelmingly, the music works composed after WWII and esteemed by academia bear a strong flavor of scholasticism which resembles that of religious scholarly traditions of pre-industrial cultures. The New Music of the West has deliberately exploited the “scientific” image in employing an invention-like approach, equating the method of strictly following a set of newly invented abstract compositional principles to mathematics (Babbitt, 2003 ). Such music usually violates the psycho-physiological restraints (Thomson, 2010 ), contributing to the public impression of its fundamental indigestibility (Lerdahl, 1992 ).

However, in toto, the situation is far from a global scientific/humanitarian schism: science does not defy humanities—it only corrects erroneous traditional beliefs. The only humanitarian discipline that consistently defies scientific methodology is Western ethnomusicology. In the past 40 years it has adopted the view that there is no such thing as “music” but myriad of “musics” (Becker, 1986 ), each requiring its unique frame of investigation (Nettl, 2010 ). The very application of a scientific method is viewed here as exercising Eurocentric political power over non-European cultures (Messner, 1993 )—seen even in merely calling a non-European artifact “music” (Bohlman, 1999 ). This highly politicized philosophy resulted in abandoning comparative studies of music systems (Savage and Brown, 2013 ), of the origins and evolution of music (Nettl, 2005 ), and of music analysis (Nattiez, 2012 ), especially pronounced in the US and UK ethnomusicological schools (Zemtsovsky, 2002 ).

General shift of Western ethnomusicology away from comparative musicology to fractured sociomusicology of isolated musical communities was inspired by concerns for compensating for the earlier Eurocentric bias in ethnographic research prior to the mid-twentieth century. Late twentieth century ethnomusicologists avoid direct comparisons between different music cultures altogether, especially those involved in establishing cultural evolution (Nettl, 2010 , p. 70–92). This revisionism relies on a systemic over-evaluation of the scope and limitations of purely emic approach to the study of music, in combination with a drastic under-evaluation of the advantages of the etic approach (see Nikolsky et al. ).

The special issue of “ The World of Music,” the journal of the International Music Council, (Vol. 22, No. 3, 1980), was dedicated to the discussion of the possibility to draw a general history of music, explore its origins, and formulate generalities in evolution of different musical cultures. Its overwhelming negative conclusions reflected the emerging trend of replacing the comparative studies that had been conducted within the field of systematic musicology by the disconnected studies of each musical culture, presumably entitled to its own unique “history” (Myers, 1993 ). Accordingly, the official name of the discipline was changed from “systematic musicology” to “ethnomusicology.” Noteworthy is the radical inversion of the views on comparative studies by the “old-timers,” such as Bruno Nettl, from positive in 1968 (Nettl and Blum, 1968 ) to negative in 2005 (Nettl, 2005 ).

Responding to Gourlay's call for ethnomusicology to abandon the “pretense of objectivity” in favor of “humanization” (Gourlay, 1982 ), Western ethnomusicologists started viewing their mission as “the study of people making music” rather than “the study of music” as the term “musicology” suggests (Titon, 2015 ). They substituted the study of text (that has traditionally been considered the “primary reality” for studying the arts) with the study of people's behaviors, causing a methodologic shift away from the analysis of music to sociology (Zemtsovsky, 1997 )—exemplified by the following quotation: “Unless the formal analysis begins as an analysis of the social situation that generates the music, it is meaningless” (Blacking, 1974 , p. 71). Analysis per se has acquired the reputation of a form of “composing” the analyzed piece of music on the part of an analyst, thereby distorting the original meaning of that music (Agawu, 2004 ). In effect, such a position deprived Western ethnomusicology of an empirical and objective foundation.

This trajectory is polarly opposite to the trend of equipping musicology with means of scientific research, prevalent in the former Soviet Bloc countries (Myers, 1993 ) 3 . Integration of scientific and humanitarian knowledge has been a long tradition there since Lobachevsky 4 (Grigoryan, 2011 )—affecting scholarship of all orientations: materialistic (Aleksei Losev), neo-Christian (Pavel Florensky), and esoteric (Peter Ouspensky). Music-related studies made no exception: noteworthy were such figures as Losev 5 , Maykapar 6 , and Samoilov 7 . All major Russian researchers of psychoacoustics could interpret/perform music at a professional level or/and compose or arrange music: Sofia Beliayeva-Ekzempliarskaya, Nikolai Garbuzov, Boris Teplov, Aleksey Ogolevets, Alexander Volodin, Yevgenii Nazaikinsky, and Yuri Rags. In 1944, Institute of History of Arts at the USSR Academy of Sciences was founded for scientific investigation of the arts (including music).

In the West too, there are ongoing attempts to bridge humanities and science by making musicology “empirical” (Clifton, 1983 ; Deutsch, 1996 ; Gjerdingen, 1999 ; Clarke and Cook, 2004 ; Honing, 2006 ; Baily, 2009 ; Schneider and Ruschkowski, 2011 ; Kendall and Lipscomb, 2013 ).

After all, every musician routinely conducts informal experiments: performers evaluate alternative ways of rendering music; studio-musicians experiment with various arrangements, and ear-trainers test students. Experimental trial of the premises of musical theory was discussed at the year-long seminar at Stanford, involving representatives of humanitarian and scientific disciplines (e.g., Lerdahl, Narmour, Gjerdingen, Bharucha, Palmer, and Krumhansl)—with the outcomes published in a special issue (1996) of “Music Perception.” Since then, this idea has attracted attention of many scholars..

This is the direction we pursue in this collection of papers. It starts with Harvey overviewing the origins of music and presenting a theory of music that reflects a “society of selves” through social cooperation. Harvey attributes the invention of music to the promotion of group coherence and personal well-being.

Montagu informs readers without music education about the capacities of early humans, their possible musical behavior, and the overall evolution of musicality. Special attention is given to the development of musical instruments, which provides a window to the reconstruction of the musicking practices of the past.

Malloch and Trevarthen present an account of music in terms of human cognition and biology, with emphasis on musical education. They show how cultural life and learning depend on the motivation for sharing projects of thought and action, musically. Music empowers the transmission of the narratives of one's “inner life” in bodily movements. This ongoing practice must have transformed the primate brain for the affective regulation of social learning, thereby determining the evolution of human musical mind.

Brown updates his widely acknowledged musilanguage theory (Brown, 2000 ) by proposing the joint prosodic origin of proto-language and proto-music, where both shared specialization in emotional communication and neither featured scaled pitches. Brown introduces a “prosodic scaffold” model—i.e., specific vocal articulations and accompanying mimics/gestures forming signs for “acoustic pantomimes,” designed to express one's affective state. According to Brown, combinatorial and compositional mechanisms of utterances generated the affective prosody, designating characteristic patterns of global acoustic expression for common emotional states. This forged into national prosody that branched into proto-language and proto-music based on, respectively, dialogic and chorusing formats of communication—distinguished by different approach to timing. At this point, music acquired concise temporal organization and synchronicity of collective production/perception.

Nikolsky introduces the term “isophony” to refer to the tonal and rhythmic properties of the musilanguage system. This amendment, endorsed by Brown, corrects the mismatch between the psychoacoustic and musicological taxonomies of musical texture. Nikolsky formulates a set of clear structural distinctions between the most common textural types: heterophony, homophony, and polyphony—in comparison to “isophony.”

van der Schyff and Schiavio overview the key positions in evolutionary musicology, identifying the problems of the nature-or-culture antithesis. They elaborate on the “biocultural” approach exemplified in the work by Tomlinson ( 2015 ), to resolve these problems. The authors examine a range of supporting evidence for this approach vs. the “embodied” approach that regards music as a bio-cultural process governed by interaction of the enacted and social aspects. The authors cross-relate the current developments in evolutionary musicology, such as “enactivism” and “4E cognition,” and suggest how the biocultural and “enactivist” approaches can be improved.

Nikolsky brings together insights from semiotics, musicology, psychoacoustics, evolutionary biology, anthropology, ethology, linguistics, and geomusicology to coin a new line of inquiry revolving around the concept of expressive aspects of music—in contradistinction from phonetics and prosody in natural languages. Central in this approach is the role of tonal organization and the comparative analysis of the acoustic features of indigenous musical traditions and animal communication calls. Nikolsky offers a new method of multifactorial modal analysis of tonal organization and its graphic representation (“musogram”) and examines its pros and cons in light of the emic/etic antithesis. He argues that music evolved from animal communication through gradual substitution of “one-ended” communication with “two-ended,” where each of multiple aspects of expression acquired a repertory of proprietary signs for effective communication of emotional information, thereby remapping the animal-like instinctive correspondences between acoustic traits and affective states. The complete “semiotization” of all principal aspects of expression must have occurred no earlier than during the Neolithic “revolution” within the framework of the emerging bi-specific communication between humans and domestic animals—exemplified in the surviving pastoral culture of kulning.

Jan proposes yet another method of musicological analysis for tracking the lineage of diachronic evolution of specific musical structures based on the memetic approach to cultural changes. Elaborating on the research by Savage ( 2016 ), Jan combines the quantitative corpus-analysis techniques, adapted from molecular biology, with qualitative method of identifying perceptual-cognitive elements of music—“musemes”—revealed by music's motivic organization. This novel humanitarian-scientific integration promises a compelling and potentially testable means for studying the cultural evolution of music.

Lumaca et al. define a new interdisciplinary field of research—the contribution of neural constraints and biases on the cultural evolution of musical structures through the chain of cultural transmissions. Capacities of the human brain constrain acquisition, production, and reproduction of music. To illustrate this, the authors demonstrate a progressive diatonization of tonal organization in the multi-generational signaling game settings, which suggests that the smaller the information-processing bottleneck in individuals, the larger the pressures to regularize the music material. This poses new intriguing questions, such as the r ole of neural variability in music diversity—which is of greatest value for folk forms of music that entirely rely on oral transmission.

Podlipniak explores the Baldwinian evolutionary modeling in search for a compelling and testable theory for the phenomenon of human musicality, hypothesizing that it might constitute an adaptive phenomenon. In the Baldwin effect, animals, learn new behaviors that allow them to survive and reproduce in the changing environment. Podlipniak argues that the increasing group size of ancestral hominins required new mechanisms of “social consolidation” in the form of “collective imitation.” There is then a natural selection for the evolution of new circuitry for vocal learning to maintain social bonds, thereby reducing the cost of learning.

Nikolsky et al. describe and explain the “timbre-based music” as a special system of musicking, communication, psychological, and social usage, along with corresponding beliefs—placing it in the timeline of the evolution of music. Timbral music opposes conventional Western music by its personal orientation: musicking here occurs primarily for oneself and/or for close relatives/friends. Throughout northeastern Eurasia, “personal song” serves as an important means of individual identification and territorial marking, akin a passport, supporting individual's mental health under harsh environmental conditions. The authors use demographic, geomusicological, paleoenvironmental, organological, and paleophonological data to argue that Siberian timbre-oriented music is remnant of the pan-Eurasian prehistoric music tradition that originated from the Last Glacial Period. Western frequency-oriented music, with its reliance on collective production/perception, might have been exported from Africa (where the population was much denser) before the LGP.

Ravignani et al. draw a parallel between researching the evolutions of music and language. They call for a systemic revaluation of an empirical and scientific approaches as opposed to claims from Chomskyan and anthropological perspectives against the scientific study. Given the intellectual influence of Chomsky, this point is extremely important. It would benefit musicologists to follow the lead of phonologists in establishing the evolutionary chain of developments. Re-aligning musicological and linguistic methodologies can allow the developmental psychologists and ethologists to make better choices between musical and linguistic paradigms in their research.

Fenk-Oczlon reports an intriguing phenomenon: the number of vowels and pitch-classes in native languages and native music tend to match. This is most pronounced in cases of simple systems—tritonic musical vs. 3-vowel vocal systems—but also noticeable in very complex 12-element systems. The mean values also match at 5–7 elements. Such correspondence supports Brown's model by revealing the shared ground between musical and vowel pitches.

Ravignani and Madison analyze the phenomenon of isochrony across human music and speech against animal communication, integrating the data from mathematics, physics, signal processing, physiology, and neuroscience. They define the concept of isochrony and propose an evolutionary hypothesis to explain why amongst all animals it is only humans that possess superb isochronous perception which does not confer evolutionary advantage to modern humans.

Honing et al. use an EEG oddball paradigm to assess the neural sensitivity to isochronous or arrhythmic beats in two monkeys. This non-invasive EEG methodology enables a direct comparison of the perception of monkeys, non-human primates, and humans. The authors found the MMN responses to the isochronous pattern but no strong evidence for beat sensitivity, confirming the Gradual Audiomotor Evolution model (Merchant and Honing, 2014 ) that holds metric organization as a biological marker of human music.

Loui et al. raise an intriguing question of musical anhedonia through cross-examination of its rare case against a panel of neurotypical participants. Their findings demonstrate the categorically different decreased connectivity between auditory and reward systems, supporting the Mixed Origins of Music model (Altenmüller et al., 2013 ). The authors identify neural pathways engaged in music's operation as an affective signaling system.

Based on his extensive teaching experience and research, Crickmore asserts his earlier experimental study and the test settings for measuring “aesthetic emotions”—listeners' response to detected “musical emotions” expressed by music creators. His revised test paves the road for clarifying the relations between human emotions, genres, and personality.

Masataka demonstrates that young people with autism spectrum disorder display more interest to dissonant music than typically developed matched group. This indicates that neural diversity within autism spectrum might have played a role in the evolution of dissonant sad music—important for overcoming negative aesthetic emotions of cognitive dissonances (Masataka and Perlovsky, 2013 ).

Trulla et al. explain consonance of musical intervals based on “second order beats,” 8 described by an approach borrowed from dynamical systems analysis—a quantitative index obtained from Recurrence Quantification Analysis. The novelty of this method is that it accounts for frequency ratio relationships plus temporal behavior. The authors confirm that musical consonance/dissonance has a mathematical foundation and that music perception, in general, and harmonic intervals, in particular, are a consequence of the entrainment of the nervous system with sound excitation.

Keller et al. provide a piece of evidence to support the Darwinian hypothesis of music's origin in sexual selection. In their study, a professional boys' choir was found to exhibit musical behavior essentially similar to male chorusing in many animal species. In female presence, bass singers instinctively emphasized and rose their singing formant—despite the conventional non-acceptance of such technique in choir-singing. This alteration, however, resulted in a more expressive performance. The authors explain this by covert competition between sexually mature males for female attention, which inadvertently maximizes choir's collective output.

We hope that this volume will bring us closer to answer Darwin's quest (Darwin, 1890 ) to disclose the mystery of music's origin.

Author Contributions

AN wrote the first draft of the manuscript. LP provided critical revision of the manuscript and important intellectual contributions. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank all the contributors of this Research Topic for their work and the high quality of the submitted articles.

1 This includes not only those papers that were submitted and published as part of our Research Topic, but also the ones that were not published (for various reasons).

2 This refers not only to the matters of music theory and the performance practices of Western forms of music, but to the undocumented implicit music theories transmitted orally by music-makers within non-Western traditional music cultures. Confused by scientific terminology, they also often see scientific approach as essentially foreign to their music practice—despite their appreciation of scholarly attention to their respective traditions.

3 Perhaps, a good demonstration of the unity of scientific and humanitarian approaches to music, common in the Soviet and modern Russian academia, is the partnership between both authors of this article: A. Nikolsky started his career as a professional composer, music theorist, and pianist, whereas L. Perlovsky—as a nuclear physicist. Somehow both authors met in their research on the origins and evolution of music.

4 Nikolai Lobachevsky outlined the principles of the ideal scholarship in his speech “On the most important subjects of education” (1828), which he delivered upon his election as the rector of the Kazan University.

5 Losev's semiotic studies eventually became most influential in the Soviet academia—laying out an encyclopedic Aristotelean-like theoretic foundation for all the disciplines in the empirical sciences and the arts. Losev's books “Music as a Subject of Logic” (1927) and “Dialectics of Artistic Form” (1927) reflected his lectures in Moscow Tchaikovsky Conservatory, where he taught aesthetics, and synthesized the neo-Platonic concept of music as a sounding number with Romantic ideas of symbolism in coining rational definitions of the notions of rhythm, melody, and harmony.

6 Maykapar ( 1900 ) was a renowned composer, an outstanding concert pianist, and a distinguished pedagogue. He pioneered Helmholtz' approach in Russia to validate and reform the traditional way of teaching and making music—which included the psychoacoustic investigation of attention, melodic intonation, rhythm, timbre, tonality, and modality (Maykapar, 1900 ).

7 Alexander Samoilov, assistant of Ivan Pavlov, and one of the developers of electrocardiography, was a virtuoso pianist and a musicologist who authored a number of publications on music theory (i.e., “Natural numbers in music,” “Musical ethnographic museum instruments and their musical tuning,” “Musical notation and its history”). He founded the Scientific-musicological Circle at Moscow University in 1902, which was later transferred to the Moscow Conservatory, where Sergei Taneyev and Samuel Maykapar subsequently took over his directorship. After moving to Kazan, Samoilov taught courses in math, physics, acoustics, music theory, and music history, in Kazan University.

8 Second order beats are perceptible when two pure tones slightly deviate from simple, small-integer ratio relationships, e.g., 2:1 (octave), 3:2 (perfect 5th), and 4:3 (perfect 4th). Deviation from simple mathematical relationships results in some degree of chaos, perceived in dissonant intervals, e.g., tritones, minor 7ths.

  • Agawu K. (2004). How we got out of analysis, and how to get back in again . Music Anal. 23 , 267–286. 10.1111/j.0262-5245.2004.00204.x [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Altenmüller E., Kopiez R., Grewe O. (2013). Strong emotions in music: are they an evolutionary adaptation? , in Sound - Perception - Performance , ed Bader R. (Heidelberg: Springer; ), 131–156. 10.1007/978-3-319-00107-4_5 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Babbitt M. (2003). The composer as specialist [Who Cares if You Listen?] , in The Collected Essays of Milton Babbitt , ed Peles S. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; ), 48–54. 10.1515/9781400841226.48 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Baily J. (2009). Crossing the boundary: from experimental psychology to ethnomusicology . Empir. Musicol. Rev. 4 , 82–88. 10.18061/1811/37484 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Becker J. (1986). Is western art music superior? Music. Q. 72 , 341–359. 10.1093/mq/LXXII.3.341 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Blacking J. (1974). How Musical Is Man? Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Bohlman P. V. (1999). Ontologies of music , in Rethinking Music , eds Cook N., Everist M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press; ), 17–34. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Brown S. (2000). The ‘musilanguage’ model of language evolution , in The Origins of Music , eds Brown S., Merker B., Wallin N. L. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ), 271–300. 10.1037/e533412004-001 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Chomsky N. (2016). What Kind of Creatures Are We? New York, NY: Columbia University Press; 10.7312/chom17596 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Clarke E. F., Cook N. (2004). Empirical Musicology: Aims, Methods, Prospects . Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Clifton T. (1983). Music as Heard: A Study in Applied Phenomenology . Cambridge, MA: Yale University Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Cohen B. R. (2001). Science and humanities: across two cultures and into science studies . Endeavour 25 , 8–12. 10.1016/S0160-9327(00)01335-1 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Darwin C. (1890). The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, 2nd Edn . London: John Murray. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Deutsch D. (1996). Preface to the special issue . Music Percept. 13 :263 10.2307/40286172 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dubal D. (1985). The World of the Concert Pianist . London: Gollancz. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Gjerdingen R. O. (1999). An experimental music theory , in Rethinking Music , eds Cook N., Everist M. (Oxford: Oxford University Press; ), 161–170. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Gould S. J. (2003). The Hedgehog, the Fox, and the Magister's Pox: Mending the Gap Between Science and the Humanities . New York, NY: Harmony Books. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Gourlay K. A. (1982). Towards a Humanizing Ethnomusicology . Ethnomusicology 26 , 411–420. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Grigoryan N. (2011). Science and art: their reciprocal advance (Наука и искусство: встречное движение) . Herald Russia. Acad. Sci. 81 , 463–467. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Honing H. (2006). On the Growing role of observation, formalization and experimental method in musicology . Empir. Musicol. Rev. 1 , 2–6. 10.18061/1811/21901 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Juslin P., Friberg A., Schoonderwaldt E., Karlsson J. (2012). Feedback learning of musical expressivity , in Musical Excellence: Strategies and Techniques to Enhance Performance , ed A. Williamon (Oxford: Oxford University Press; ), 247–270. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198525356.001.0001 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kendall R. A., Lipscomb S. D. (2013). Experimental semiotics applied to visual, sound, and musical structures , in The Psychology of Music in Multimedia (Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press; ), 48–65. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199608157.003.0003 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lerdahl F. (1992). Cognitive constraints on compositional systems . Contemp. Music Rev. 6 , 97–121. 10.1080/07494469200640161 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Masataka N., Perlovsky L. (2013). Cognitive interference can be mitigated by consonant music and facilitated by dissonant music . Sci. Rep. 3 :2028. 10.1038/srep02028 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Maykapar S. (1900). Musical Hearing, Its Significance, Specialty and Method of Correct Development [Музыкальный слух. Его значение, природа, особенности и метод правильного развития]. Moscow: Jurgenson; [Юргенсон]. [ Google Scholar ]
  • McGinn C. (2015). Inborn Knowledge: The Mystery Within . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Merchant H., Honing H. (2014). Are non-human primates capable of rhythmic entrainment? Evidence for the gradual audiomotor evolution hypothesis . Front. Neurosci. 7 :274. 10.3389/fnins.2013.00274 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Messner G. F. (1993). Ethnomusicological research, another “performance” in the international year of indigenous peoples? World Music 35 , 81–95. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Myers H. (1993). Ethnomusicology: Historical and Regional Studies . New York, NY: Norton. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Nattiez J.-J. (2012). Is the search for universals incompatible with the study of cultural specificity? Hum. Soc. Stud. 1 , 67–94. 10.2478/v10317-012-0005-2 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Nettl B. (2005). The Study of Ethnomusicology: Thirty-One Issues and Concepts . Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Nettl B. (2010). Nettl's Elephant: On the History of Ethnomusicology . Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Nettl B., Blum S. (1968). Towards the comparative study of the structure of traditional repertoires . J. Int. Folk Music Council . 20 , 47–50. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Parncutt R. (2017). The two cultures in German translation: humanities, science, and Wissenschaft . Scott. Music Rev . 4 Available online at: https://www.n-ism.org/SMR/Parncutt:_Wissenschaft.pdf
  • Regelski T. A. (2014). Scientism in experimental music research . Philos. Music Educ. Rev. 4 , 3–19. 10.2307/40327103 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Savage P. E. (2016). Measuring the cultural evolution of music: with case studies of British-American and Japanese folk, art, and popular music (dissertation) . Department of Musicology, Tokyo University of the Arts, 120. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Savage P. E., Brown S. (2013). Toward a new comparative musicology . Anal. Approach. World Music 2 , 148–197. 10.31234/osf.io/q3egp [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Schneider A., Ruschkowski A. von. (2011). Systematic Musicology: Empirical and Theoretical Studies . Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang Verlag; 10.3726/978-3-653-01290-3 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Snow C. P. (1964). The Two Cultures . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Thomson W. E. (2010). Empirical musicology review: serialist claims versus sonic reality . Empir. Musicol. Rev. 5 , 36–50. 10.18061/1811/46748 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Titon J. T. (2015). Ethnomusicology as the study of people making music . Muzikoloski Zbornik 51 , 175–185. 10.4312/mz.51.2.175-185 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Tomlinson G. (2015). A million Years of Music: The Emergence of Human Modernity . New York, NY: Zone Books. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Wallin N. L., Merker B., Brown S. (1999). The Origins of Music . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Wilson E. O. (1998). Consilience: The Unity of knowledge . New York, NY: Knopf. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Woody R. H. (2000). Learning expressivity in music performance: an exploratory study . Res. Stud. Music Educ. 14 , 14–23. 10.1177/1321103X0001400102 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Woody R. H. (2004). 5 Misconceptions about scientific research in music education . Teach. Music 11 , 28–33. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Zemtsovsky I. (1997). An attempt at a synthetic paradigm . Ethnomusicology 41 , 185–205. 10.2307/852602 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Zemtsovsky I. (2002). The apologia of text [Апология текста] . Music. Acad . [Музыкальная академия] 4 , 100–110. Available online at: https://mus.academy/articles/apologiya-teksta [ Google Scholar ]

Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs faces sweeping sex-trafficking inquiry: What the feds have, need to prove

Law enforcement officers and cars on a street with police tape.

  • Show more sharing options
  • Copy Link URL Copied!

Over the last few months, a legendary name in the music world has faced a series of shocking allegations of sexual abuse.

In civil lawsuits, four women have accused Sean “Diddy” Combs of rape, assault and other abuses, dating back three decades. One of the allegations involved a minor. The claims sent shock waves through the music industry and put Combs’ entertainment empire in jeopardy.

Now, the hip-hop mogul’s legal troubles have worsened considerably.

Law enforcement sources told The Times that Combs is the subject of a sweeping inquiry into sex-trafficking allegations that resulted in a federal raid Monday at his estates in Los Angeles and Miami.

A law enforcement agent carries a bag of evidence to a van as federal agents stand at the entrance to a property belonging to rapper Sean "Diddy" Combs, Monday, March 25, 2024, on Star Island in Miami Beach, Fla. Two properties belonging to Combs in Los Angeles and Miami were searched Monday by federal Homeland Security Investigations agents and other law enforcement as part of an ongoing sex trafficking investigation by federal authorities in New York, two law enforcement officials told The Associated Press. (AP Photo/Rebecca Blackwell)

Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs’ L.A., Miami homes raided in sex-trafficking inquiry, sources say

Agents search Sean Combs’ Holmby Hills and Miami mansions as part of a federal inquiry into sex trafficking allegations, law enforcement sources said.

March 26, 2024

Authorities have declined to comment on the case, and Combs has not been charged with any crime. But the scene of dozens of Department of Homeland Security agents — guns drawn — searching Combs’ properties underscored the seriousness of the investigation.

At the same time as the raids, police in Miami arrested Brendan Paul, a man described in a recent lawsuit against Combs as a confidant and drug “mule.” Miami-Dade police took Paul, 25, into custody on suspicion of possession of cocaine and a controlled substance-laced candy, records show.

Paul was arrested at Miami Opa-Locka Executive Airport, where TMZ posted video showing Combs walking around Monday afternoon. An affidavit reviewed by the Miami Herald alleged that police working with Homeland Security found drugs in Paul’s bag. There is nothing in Miami court records connecting Combs to Paul, who was later released on $2,500 bail.

The arrest, however, is the latest in a string of legal woes tied to Combs.

Sources with knowledge of the sex-trafficking investigation into Combs, who spoke on condition of anonymity because they were not authorized to speak publicly, said federal authorities have interviewed at least three women, but it’s unclear whether any are among those who have filed suit.

Photo illustration of Sean Diddy Combs with half his face falling into small square pieces

Behind the calamitous fall of hip-hop mogul Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs

In the wake of multiple lawsuits filed against him, former members of Combs’ inner circle told The Times that his alleged misconduct against women goes back decades.

Dec. 13, 2023

Legal experts say it could take time to build a criminal case against Combs but note that the civil suits could offer investigators a road map.

Dmitry Gorin, a former L.A. County sex-crimes prosecutor who is now in private practice, said the allegations in the lawsuits would likely have been enough for a judge to grant search warrants for Combs’ homes.

Investigators probably would seek authorization to “search for videos or photographs on any devices connected to the target ... anywhere where digital images can be found in connection to sexual conduct that would have been recorded,” Gorin said.

Shawn Holley, an attorney for Combs, did not respond to requests for comment, but Aaron Dyer, another of his lawyers, on Tuesday called the raids a “witch hunt” and “a gross overuse of military-level force.”

“Yesterday, there was a gross overuse of military-level force as search warrants were executed at Mr. Combs’ residences,” Dyer said in a statement. “This unprecedented ambush — paired with an advanced, coordinated media presence — leads to a premature rush to judgment of Mr. Combs and is nothing more than a witch hunt based on meritless accusations made in civil lawsuits. There has been no finding of criminal or civil liability with any of these allegations.”

Combs has previously denied any wrongdoing.

Sean Combs arrives at a pre-Grammy party

Gorin and other legal experts said investigators could be focused, in part, on the sexual assault allegations involving a minor. If a minor is moved across state lines for the purpose of sex, “that is enough for at least an argument ... of sex trafficking because somebody underage cannot consent,” Gorin said.

“Sex trafficking for adults usually involves some sort of coercion or other restraints,” he said, and can be tougher to prove. Prosecutors would need to show you “encouraged somebody to engage in sexual activity for money or some other inducement.”

Coercion, he added, is not limited to threats of violence. It could involve being held against one’s will or someone simply saying, “I don’t want to participate in group sex, and now I’m being forced to.”

Homeland Security investigates most sex-trafficking operations for the federal government. Legal experts say one possibility why the agency could be involved in this case is because the women involved in the allegations against Combs could be from other countries.

Sean "Diddy" Combs wears a satiny red puffer suit while holding a microphone onstage with two hands

Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs sexual harassment suit includes notable music industry names

A new suit from music producer Rodney “Lil Rod” Jones makes new, explosive claims about Combs’ alleged assaults and misconduct in granular detail, naming several prominent artists and music executives as well.

Feb. 28, 2024

Meghan Blanco, a defense attorney who has handled sexual trafficking cases, said they can be “incredibly difficult cases to prove.”

“They have [in the Combs case] convinced one or more federal magistrates they had enough probable cause for one or more search warrants,” Blanco said. “Given the scope of the investigation, it seems they are further along than most investigations.”

Combs’ legal troubles have been building for months.

His former girlfriend, Casandra Ventura, the singer known as Cassie, accused him of rape and repeated physical assaults and said he forced her to have sex with male prostitutes in front of him. Joi Dickerson-Neal accused Combs in a suit of drugging and raping her in 1991, recording the attack and then distributing the footage without her consent.

Liza Gardner filed a third suit in which she claimed Combs and R&B singer Aaron Hall sexually assaulted her. Hall could not be reached for comment.

Another lawsuit alleges that Combs and former Bad Boy label president Harve Pierre gang-raped and sex-trafficked a 17-year-old girl. Pierre said in a statement that the allegations were “disgusting,” “false” and a “desperate attempt for financial gain.”

After the filing of the fourth suit, Combs wrote on Instagram: “Enough is enough. For the last couple of weeks, I have sat silently and watched people try to assassinate my character, destroy my reputation and my legacy. Sickening allegations have been made against me by individuals looking for a quick payday. Let me be absolutely clear: I did not do any of the awful things being alleged. I will fight for my name, my family and for the truth.”

Last month, producer Rodney “Lil Rod” Jones filed a federal lawsuit against Combs accusing him of sexually harassing and threatening him for more than a year. The suit includes mention of Paul in connection with “the affairs ... involving dealing in controlled substances.”

On Monday, the suit was amended to include Oscar winner Cuba Gooding Jr. as a co-defendant in the lawsuit.

Sean "Diddy" Combs holds an award up and cheers.

Cuba Gooding Jr. added as co-defendant in Lil Rod’s lawsuit against Diddy

Cuba Gooding Jr. is added as a co-defendant in a lawsuit against Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs. Record producer Rodney ‘Lil Rod’ Jones accuses the actor of sexual assault.

Blanco said prosecutors “are going to look carefully for corroboration — the numbers of people accusing the person of similar acts.” Beyond that, they will be looking for videos, recordings and cellphone records that place people in the same locations or text messages or other discussions at the time of the alleged acts.

She said prosecutors are trying to build a record of incidents that happened some time ago.

Douglas Wigdor, a lawyer for Ventura and another, unnamed plaintiff, said in response to reports of the search warrant issued against Combs: “We will always support law enforcement when it seeks to prosecute those that have violated the law. Hopefully, this is the beginning of a process that will hold Mr. Combs responsible for his depraved conduct.”

Wigdor on Tuesday called his clients “courageous and credible witnesses.”

“To the extent there is a prosecution and they want our clients to testify truthfully,” he said, “I think they will and that will be damning evidence.”

The searches Monday in L.A. and Miami sparked worldwide attention.

Sean Combs arrives at a pre-Grammy party

Diddy’s ‘Love’ producer Lil Rod accuses him and associates of sexual assault, illicit behavior

Rodney ‘Lil Rod’ Jones has filed a bombshell lawsuit against Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs accusing the media mogul of sexually harassing and threatening him.

Feb. 27, 2024

His 17,000-square-foot Holmby Hills mansion, where Combs debuted his last album a year ago, was flooded with Homeland Security agents who gathered evidence on behalf of an investigation being run by the Southern District of New York, according to law enforcement officials familiar with the inquiry.

Two of Combs’ sons were briefly detained at the Holmby Hills property as agents searched the mansion in footage captured by FOX11 Los Angeles.

Both Blanco and Gorin said prosecutors will have to examine the accusers’ motives for coming forward and whether they are motivated by financial gain. They are sure to look for inconsistencies in any allegations, they said.

Any defense, Blanco added, will question why the accusers are only now coming forward and whether they have an incentive beyond justice.

“It comes down to credibility,” she said.

Times staff writers Stacy Perman and Nardine Saad contributed to this report.

More to Read

Sean "Diddy" Combs

Feds want Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs’ communications, flight records in sex-trafficking probe

March 29, 2024

Left, Daphne Joy. Right, Rapper 50 Cent.

50 Cent denies Daphne Joy’s rape allegation after trolling her over mention in Diddy lawsuit

A law enforcement officer leads out a canine as federal agents stand at the entrance to a property belonging to rapper Sean "Diddy" Combs, Monday, March 25, 2024, on Star Island in Miami Beach, Fla. Two properties belonging to Combs in Los Angeles and Miami were searched Monday by federal Homeland Security Investigations agents and other law enforcement as part of an ongoing sex trafficking investigation by federal authorities in New York, two law enforcement officials told The Associated Press. (AP Photo/Rebecca Blackwell)

Inside the Sean ‘Diddy’ Combs’ raids: Emptied safes, dismantled electronics, gun-toting feds

March 28, 2024

Start your day right

Sign up for Essential California for news, features and recommendations from the L.A. Times and beyond in your inbox six days a week.

You may occasionally receive promotional content from the Los Angeles Times.

essay on music wikipedia

Richard Winton is an investigative crime writer for the Los Angeles Times and part of the team that won the Pulitzer Prize for public service in 2011. Known as @lacrimes on Twitter, during almost 30 years at The Times he also has been part of the breaking news staff that won Pulitzers in 1998, 2004 and 2016.

More From the Los Angeles Times

Shaylee Mejia with her little brother. (Maria Juarez)

A South L.A. teen died after a fight at school. Officials ruled the death an accident. What comes next?

March 30, 2024

Alex (pictured) and Daisy De La Rosa decided to fill the potholes in their community but the city of Compton wants them to stop.

A Compton couple fixed neighborhood potholes. The city has ordered them to stop

LOS ANGELES, CA - JULY 20: Maria Menjivar, center, owner of Las Palmitas Mini Market, flanked by granddaughters, Sarai Palacios, 14, left, Natalia Palacios, 9, right, Navor Herrera, far left, and Angelica Menjivar, owner with mother Maria, pose for a photo at Las Palmitas Mini Market where a $1-billion Powerball ticket was sold in downtown on Thursday, July 20, 2023 in Los Angeles, CA. The winner, who remains unidentified, purchased their ticket at Las Palmitas Mini Market at East 12th Street and Wall Street. (Gary Coronado / Los Angeles Times)

Winner of $1-billion Powerball has been revealed. Another jackpot is up for grabs

OAKLAND, CA - FEB. 16: Surveillance cameras are seen mounted on an overhead storefront sign in the Chinatown district of Oakland, California Tuesday, Feb. 16, 2021. Community members are on heightened alert after the recent increase in violent crimes, many caught on camera, toward the Asian American community throughout the Bay Area. Despite an increased police presence, armed private security, and volunteer groups patrolling the area around Oakland Chinatown, many businesses continue to worry and are taking extra precautionary measures such as boarding up storefronts and closing hours earlier despite how the pandemic-driven economic downturn has already impacted many. (Stephen Lam/The San Francisco Chronicle via Getty Images)

To catch a thief: Oakland installs hundreds of surveillance cameras to try to thwart crime

  • Share full article

Advertisement

Supported by

Steve Harley, ‘Make Me Smile’ Singer, Dies at 73

He was the frontman of the rock band Cockney Rebel, which landed several hits on the British charts in the 1970s.

A beaded man in a black vest and purple-and-white striped shirt with a guitar on a knee and an arm raised above his head.

By Orlando Mayorquín

Steve Harley, the 1970s British rock star who topped Britain’s music charts with the single “Make Me Smile,” died on Sunday at his home in Suffolk, England. He was 73.

H is family announced the death on Facebook. No cause was given, but Mr. Harley had announced last month that he would step away from the stage to undergo treatment for cancer and had previously canceled several concerts scheduled for this year.

Mr. Harley was the frontman of the band Cockney Rebel, which he formed in the early 1970s.

His biggest hit was the 1975 single “Make Me Smile,” in which Mr. Harley’s even-keeled vocals and melancholic lyrics cruise over an instrumental backing that bears the optimistic sound distinct to bands of the era. The song hit the top of the British charts in February of that year .

Cockney Rebel’s other British hits included the 1974 single “Judy Teen,” which peaked at No. 5 on the charts that year , and a funky cover of the Beatles’ “Here Comes the Sun” in 1976.

Other songs found success outside Britain.

“Sebastian,” a single featured on the band’s debut album, “The Human Menagerie,” released in 1973, became a No. 1 hit in Belgium and the Netherlands, according to Mr. Harley’s website.

In 1986, Mr. Harley and the singer Sarah Brightman made the first recording of “Phantom of the Opera,” the title song from the musical of the same name by Andrew Lloyd Webber.

Steve Harley was born on Feb. 27, 1951, in London and was, according to his online biography, the second of five children. His mother, who was a jazz singer in the 1940s, offered Mr. Harley one of his earliest introductions to music.

“She sang around the house when we were kids,” he said in a 2015 interview for the Tim Quinn YouTube channel, comparing his mother’s voice to that of Anne Shelton, a British vocalist who was popular during World War II.

When he was a child, his mother would sing along to Buddy Holly and other 1950s pop singers who would play on the radio, he said in the interview.

Complete information on survivors was not immediately available.

An illness and surgeries kept Mr. Harley rotating in and out of the hospital as a child. At age 12, while recovering from surgery, he found an affinity for the works of D.H. Lawrence, Ernest Hemingway and other authors and took a liking to Bob Dylan’s music, according to his online biography.

These artists, his website said, “moved a young Mr. Harley to realize that his life would likely be “preoccupied with words and music.”

He indeed became preoccupied with words in the late 1960s and early ’70s as he pursued a career in journalism, working for several daily newspapers in Britain.

Around the same time, his life as a singer was born in London nightclubs, where he would perform free, and where he met his eventual Cockney Rebel bandmates, with whom he struck the band’s first record deal in 1972.

A prolific performer, Mr. Harley continued singing days into his final years. He took the stage as recently as 2023.

An earlier version of this obituary misstated the year Mr. Harley gave an interview for the Tim Quinn YouTube channel. It was 2015 — not 2022, when the interview was posted online.

How we handle corrections

Orlando Mayorquín is a breaking news reporter, based in New York, and a member of the 2023-24 Times Fellowship class , a program for journalists early in their careers. More about Orlando Mayorquín

IMAGES

  1. Essay on Music

    essay on music wikipedia

  2. Write an essay on Music in english

    essay on music wikipedia

  3. Essay on Music

    essay on music wikipedia

  4. How to Write a Music Essay: Topics and Examples

    essay on music wikipedia

  5. Music essay

    essay on music wikipedia

  6. How to Write a Music Essay: Topics and Examples

    essay on music wikipedia

VIDEO

  1. Essay Music Video Banjul

  2. What is the Greatest Song?

  3. Faithful Love

  4. My Favorite Music Documentaries

  5. The Language of Music

  6. The Music That Defined James Bond

COMMENTS

  1. Music

    v. t. e. In the most general of terms, music is the arrangement of sound to create some combination of form, harmony, melody, rhythm, or otherwise expressive content. [1] [2] [3] Definitions of music vary depending on culture, [4] though it is an aspect of all human societies and a cultural universal. [5]

  2. History of music

    During the 9th century, several important developments took place. First, there was a major effort by the Church to unify the many chant traditions and suppress many of them in favor of the Gregorian liturgy. Second, the earliest polyphonic music was sung, a form of parallel singing known as organum.

  3. Philosophy of music

    Philosophy of music is the study of "fundamental questions about the nature and value of music and our experience of it". The philosophical study of music has many connections with philosophical questions in metaphysics and aesthetics.The expression was born in the 19th century and has been used especially as the name of a discipline since the 1980s.

  4. The Philosophy of Music

    First published Mon Oct 22, 2007; substantive revision Mon Oct 30, 2023. Philosophy of music is the study of fundamental questions about the nature and value of music and our experience of it. Like any "philosophy of X," it presupposes knowledge of its target. However, unlike philosophy of science, say, the target of philosophy of music is ...

  5. Music

    music, art concerned with combining vocal or instrumental sounds for beauty of form or emotional expression, usually according to cultural standards of rhythm, melody, and, in most Western music, harmony.Both the simple folk song and the complex electronic composition belong to the same activity, music. Both are humanly engineered; both are conceptual and auditory, and these factors have been ...

  6. Music

    A painting on an Ancient Greek vase shows a music lesson (about 510 BC) The Estonian Symphony Orchestra in Stockholm, 2008 Paco de Lucena, 19th-century Spanish gypsy flamenco guitarist Horn Music. Music is a form of art that uses sound organised in time.Music is also a form of entertainment that puts sounds together in a way that people like, find interesting or dance to.

  7. The story of music is the story of humans

    How Music and Instruments Began: A Brief Overview of the Origin and Entire Development of Music, from Its Earliest Stages. Frontiers in Sociology , 2017; 2 DOI: 10.3389/fsoc.2017.00008 Cite This ...

  8. History of Western Philosophy of Music: Antiquity to 1800

    ---, 1988, The Idea of Music: An Introduction to Musical Aesthetics in Antiquity and the Middle Ages, Kalamazoo, MI: Medieval Institute Publications, Western Michigan University. Scott, John T. (ed.), 1998, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Essay on the Origin of Language and Writings related to Music, Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.

  9. A General History of Music

    I - The Progress of Music in ENGLAND during the Time of King Henry VIII. CHAP. II - Of the State of Music in ITALY during the Sixteenth Century: including an Account of Theorists, with the Progress of practical Music in the Church, as well as of Madrigals, Ricercati, or Fantasias, and secular Songs of that Period. CHAP.

  10. Charles Rosen's Freedom and the Arts: Essays on Music and Literature

    The critic, historian, music theorist, and virtuosic pianist Charles Rosen has spent the past half century examining this question, and his latest book, Freedom and the Arts: Essays on Music and Literature, a collection of 28 essays written mainly over the past 15 years, is his most expansive analysis to date of the challenges and pleasures of ...

  11. PDF Writing about Music: A Guide to Writing in A & I 24

    Writing about music, like writing about any subject, takes place in stages. "Listen-ing to Music," the guide included in your sourcepack, details a procedure that will help you know the music well enough to write about it for your First Nightspapers. In brief, prior to developing the thesis and planning the structure of an essay, you

  12. Writing An Essay On Music Thematic: 5 Key Elements

    1) Writing about music that you love: Whether it's disco or desert-rock, EDM or classical, if you choose a genre or subject you love, the process of writing becomes much easier. All those internal references and resonances can come out in an essay and help demonstrate how much of an expert you are on your theme of choice.

  13. What is the Purpose of Music?

    Communicates emotions. The hypothesis that music played an essential role in the formation and survival of groups and in conflict mitigation is one of the most widely accepted. Mark Tramo of the Institute for Music & Brain Science at Harvard University defines it as a factor of social cohesion. "Men needed to organise to hunt and defend ...

  14. Music theory

    Music theory. Theory of Music is all about trying to understand how existing music works and how new music could or should be organized. Someone who makes a special study of music theory is a music theorist . People who make their own music are composers. People who play or sing music are "performers". It is important for both composers and ...

  15. How to Write a Great College Essay About Music (with examples)

    Key Takeaway. When writing a college essay about music, it's important to avoid cliches and approach the topic in a deeply personal and meaningful way. Whether you focus on music as an academic interest or a significant extracurricular, you should show off your intellectual spark or personal strengths. Ask any admissions officer if they've ...

  16. Essay on Music for Students and Children

    500+ Words Essay on Music. Music is a vital part of different moments of human life. It spreads happiness and joy in a person's life. Music is the soul of life and gives immense peace to us. In the words of William Shakespeare, "If music is the food of love, play on, Give me excess of it; that surfeiting, The appetite may sicken, and so die

  17. Soul music

    soul music, term adopted to describe African American popular music in the United States as it evolved from the 1950s to the '60s and '70s. Some view soul as merely a new term for rhythm and blues. In fact a new generation of artists profoundly reinterpreted the sounds of the rhythm-and-blues pioneers of the 1950s— Chuck Berry, Little ...

  18. Editorial: The Evolution of Music

    1 This includes not only those papers that were submitted and published as part of our Research Topic, but also the ones that were not published (for various reasons).. 2 This refers not only to the matters of music theory and the performance practices of Western forms of music, but to the undocumented implicit music theories transmitted orally by music-makers within non-Western traditional ...

  19. Jazz

    The music that eventually became jazz evolved out of a wide-ranging, gradually assimilated mixture of Black and white folk musics and popular styles, with roots in both West Africa and Europe. It is only a slight oversimplification to assert that the rhythmic and structural elements of jazz, as well as some aspects of its customary instrumentation (e.g., banjo or guitar and percussion), derive ...

  20. World music

    "World music" is an English phrase for styles of music from non-Western countries, including quasi-traditional, ... This section is written like a personal reflection, personal essay, or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor's personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic.

  21. Hip-hop

    hip-hop, cultural movement that attained widespread popularity in the 1980s and '90s and also the backing music for rap, the musical style incorporating rhythmic and/or rhyming speech that became the movement's most lasting and influential art form.. Origins and the old school. Although widely considered a synonym for rap music, the term hip-hop refers to a complex culture comprising four ...

  22. Inside the sex-trafficking investigation into Sean 'Diddy' Combs

    Over the last few months, a legendary name in the music world has faced a series of shocking allegations of sexual abuse.. In civil lawsuits, four women have accused Sean "Diddy" Combs of rape ...

  23. Essay

    Definitions John Locke's 1690 An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. The word essay derives from the French infinitive essayer, "to try" or "to attempt".In English essay first meant "a trial" or "an attempt", and this is still an alternative meaning. The Frenchman Michel de Montaigne (1533-1592) was the first author to describe his work as essays; he used the term to characterize these as ...

  24. Steve Harley, 'Make Me Smile' Singer, Dies at 73

    Roberto Ricciuti/Redferns. Steve Harley, the 1970s British rock star who topped Britain's music charts with the single "Make Me Smile," died on Sunday at his home in Suffolk, England. He was ...

  25. Odissi music

    Odissi music (Odia: ଓଡ଼ିଶୀ ସଙ୍ଗୀତ, romanized: oṛiśī sangīta, Odia: [oɽisi sɔŋgit̪ɔ] ⓘ) is a genre of classical music in India, originated from the eastern state of Odisha.The traditional ritual music for the service of Lord Jagannatha, Odissi music has a history spanning over two thousand years, authentic sangita-shastras or treatises, unique Ragas & Talas ...